Skip to main content

Full text of "Christianity and Civilisation: Part 2, Specific Problems - Emil Brunner"

See other formats


Press Opinions on Part I 

" A masterly philosophical survey of the problems of ontology and truth " — 
Observe}. 

" It is impossible to exaggerate the interest and value of these Lectures " — 
Manchester Guardian. 

" Marked by lucidity and ease of exposition . . . One of the most distinguished 
Continental theologians of our time " — Spectator. 

" For one reader at any rate, this is 4 the book of the year ' 55 — Holborn Review. 



CHRISTIANITY 

AND 
CIVILISATION 

By 

EMIL BRUNNER 

SECOND PART : 

SPECIFIC PROBLEMS 

GIFFORX) LECTURES DELIVERED AT 
THE UNIVERSITY OF ST. ANDREWS 
1948 




LONDON: NISBET & CO., LTD. 
22 BERNERS STREET, W.i 



First published in igqq 



Made and printed in Great Britain 



PREFACE 



THIS second series of my Gifford Lectures, given at St. 
Andrews University in March 1948, is complementary to 
the first. While the first was an attempt to work out 
something like a Christian philosophy of civilisation dealing with 
some basic principles which underlie all civilisation, it is the 
scope of this sacond series to give a Christian interpretation of 
some of the main features of civilised life. Many readers may 
miss some other aspects, such as marriage and the family, which 
they feel of equal if not of greater importance than those treated 
in this book. If-,so, I completely agree with them, but having 
been compelled to restrict myself to nine such subjects (in the 
tenth lecture I attempt to give a synoptic view of the whole 
field), I think it justifiable to leave out some of the topics which 
have been in the focus of Christian thought throughout the 
ages as well as in recent times. 

As a matter of fact, I am not so much afraid of the reproach 
of having treated too few, but rather of the criticism of those 
who think I have tried to deal with too many subjects. I hear 
them ask how any one man can claim to have competent 
knowledge of so many different sectors of civilisation, each being 
almost infinite in itself. Again I fully share this view. There 
is probably no one — at any rate not the author — who can make 
such a claim. Still, it so happens that my life is concerned with 
all of these sectors and I have to try to lead it as a Christian, and 
the same is true of thousands of my contemporaries. While it 
is necessary that Christian men and women particularly com- 
petent in one of these fields should speak and write about the 
relation of the Christian faith to that particular matter, it seems 
to me legitimate, and even necessary, that alongside these mono- 
graphs of specialists someone should at least try to give a 
synoptic view of the whole (even if he has no expert knowledge 



* v 



VI PREFACE 

of a majority of these subjects), provided that he has given 
to all of them prolonged thought as a Christian. 

Perhaps I would not have dared to form such a plan had I 
not, in lecturing about one of those subjects' which is particularly 
remote from my own experience — that of technics, or should I 
say technology? — received much encouragement from groups of 
experts, both professors and practical technicians. None the 
less, I am sure that in every one of these lectures there is much 
to be criticised by those who do have expert knowledge in that 
particular field. They may be assured that they will find me 
sincerely grateful for their criticisms; indeed I have been so 
conscious of the inadequacy of my knowledge and my lack of 
experience that on several occasions I have felt* like giving up 
altogether. 

This view of my task made it imperative not to try to give my 
lectures an apparent weight of scholarship by quoting many 
books. The only scholarship to which I mighf lay claim is that 
of a theologian or Christian thinker, who has made up his mind 
to apply some of the basic Christian doctrines to some of the 
problems of civilisation or culture, of which the urgency is felt 
by every live Christian. 

The brevity of these lectures, compared with those of most of 
my predecessors, is mainly due to the fact that for reasons of 
language I could not afford to prepare two sets of lectures, one 
for fifty minutes' delivery, the other for publication. Even 
within this limitation I should not have succeeded had I not 
received most generous help from colleagues at St. Andrews, 
particularly Professor Donald Baillie and Professor W. R. 
Forrester. Again I wish to thank many other good friends, both 
within and outside St. Mary's College, for thejyr sympathy and 
hospitality, which made my stay in their town a happy 
experience which I shall not forget. 

E. B. 



CONTENTS 

PREFACE 



v 



I. TECHNICS i 

Technics as old as man. The problem of technics new, 
resulting from the technical revolution. Technic^ man 
precedes technical revolution. Robinson Crusoe. Effects 
of the technical revolution on man. The tragic coincidence : 
technical revolution in the age of secularisation. Means 
and ends reversed. The spiritual cause of this reversal. 
The fata> course of technics — towards the abyss ? Ethical 
appeal and education inadequate. The Christian alternative 
to the technical apocalypse. 

II. SCIENCE 1 6 

Science ^ounger than technics. Its relation to truth. 
Natural science and Geisteswissenschqften. The scientific 
ethos. Its Christian basis. No necessary conflict with faith. 
The influence of sin upon science. Scientific mythology. 
Science and the postulate of " religious neutrality The 
value of Christian anthropology for the Geisteswissenschqften. 
Science within the totality of human destiny. 

III. TRADITION AND RENEWAL .... 29 

The modern age anti-traditional. Tradition : cultural 
memory. Christianity and tradition. Christianity guardian 
of Greek cultural values. Social tradition and social rootless- 
ness. Christianity and change. <c Not yet " and *' no more 
The newness of life in the Gospel. The revolutionary force 
of Christian faith. Renewal of centre and periphery. Revolu- 
tionary conservatism. 

IV. EDUCATION 43 

Education and community. The Socratic programme of 
education. Its incomparable influence. Its relation to 
Christianity. The German idealist idea of Bildung* 
Its aristocratic character. The original Christian idea of 
education. Its deformation by theological intellectualism. 
The Reformation ignores the Socratic element. Pestalozzi's 
rediscovery. Kierkegaard's contribution. Secularist educa- 
tion in our age. The Christian idea in the modern setting. 

<» vii 



WORK 



57 



Why do men work? The classical (Aristotelian) con- 
ception of work. Its influence in the middle ages. The 
Marxist idea its counterpart. Luther's Rediscovery <$f voca- 
tion. The modern crisis of the " motifs " of work. Its essential 
causes. Collectivism unable to restore the dignity of work. 
The Christian conception of work, both as stimulus and as 
moderating force. 

. ART 72 

Comprehensive conception of " art The mystery of 
art deeper than beauty. Imaginary elevation of existence. 
The danger of aestheticism. The second commandment. 
" Christian art " ? Form primary in art, but art presupposes 
human depth. Art in relation to Roman Catholic and 
Protestant religion. Can art survive secularism? The 
metaphysical basis of passion. Formalism and barbarism. 
Art and " the sabbath 

VII. WEALTH • . . 86 

Material presuppositions of cultural life. Personality and 
property. The abstract material good, money and credit. 
Its danger for personality and community. Capitalism 
according to Marx. Wealth in the light of the Bible. No 
Biblical system of economics. Ethical interest in economic 
structure. Communism necessarily totalitarian. The dilemma 
of social security and the free society. Christianity and the 
economic motif. Onesidedness of Max Weber's theory con- 
cerning Calvinistic capitalism. Christianity and secularist 
materialism. 

VIII. SOCIAL CUSTOM (SITTE) AND LAW . 101 

Destruction of social habit by individualistic rationalism. 
Social habit basis of personal morality. The New Testament 
and social habit. Along with artistic " style " social habit 
destroyed in the last century. Law filling tlje gap. Natural 
and positive law. Positivism. Pre-state and state-Law. 
Gospel and Law. The created order. Equal rights in 
Stoicism and Christianity, Polarity of personal rights and 
social obligation. Law and sin. Secularism increases co- 
ercive law. 

. POWER . 114 

Restrictive definition. Having and using power. Will-to- 
power. Material and spiritual elements in power. Power 



CONTENTS IX 

and freedom. Limiting and monopolising ultimate power, 
the state. The " division of power 9 \ State sovereignty and 
God-so¥ereignty. ^ The unlimited state power, the totalitarian 
state. Power in inter-state relations. The attempts to limit 
national sovereignty. The universal world state in the light 
of Christian faith. Culture, power and religion. 

X. THE CHRISTIAN IDEA OF CIVILISATION 

AND CULTURE 127 

Coming back to the first lecture. What can Christian 
civilisation mean ? Man alone produces civilisation. Essence 
of civilisation. Its basic motifs. Civilisation human, but not the 
Human. Why it is 4 c formal ". The place of civilisation and 
culture in the Christian conception of life. Some objections 
answered.^ The Christian idea : the human above the cul- 
tural ; the physical-spiritual unity of man ; the civic ele- 
ment fundamental, therefore civilisation above culture. 
The place of tradition and education. The " highest cultural 
values " — how far ? Art and science in the service of God 
and of man. The present chances for the realisation of the 
Christian idea. 



EPILOGUE. CHRISTIANITY BEYOND 

CIVILISATION 140 



CHRfSTIANITY AND CIVILISATION 



Second Part : Specific Problems 
I 

TECHNICS 1 

A MONGST all the problems of civilisation with which we 
l\ are dealing in these lectures, the problem of " technics " 
JL JL is the youngest. All the others have worried Western 
mankind and Christianity for centuries; not so technics. In 
earlier times people had hardly become conscious of it, much 
less did they think of it as a problem. To-day, however, it is 
in the front line, because — to a degree previously unheard of — 
technics — or shall I say technology? — determines the life of 
man, endangers the human character of civilisation, and even 
threatens the very existence of mankind. Whilst half a century 
ago the startling progress of technology was the basis of an 
optimistic philosophy of life and progress, since the two world 
wars, and particularly since the first atomic bomb was dropped 
on Hiroshima, the conception of technics has become more and 
more connected with gloomy, even desperate, perspectives for 
the future. The question whether civilisation and mankind will 
survive has become the problem of the hour, so that we cannot 
but start with it. 

This fact — that technology has recently become the most 
urgent of all problems — contrasts strangely with the other fact 
that technics is as old as humanity. Human history begins with 
the invention of the first stone tool, that is, with technics. It is 
in the shape of homo faber that man first shows himself as a 
being transcending nature. From this beginning technics, that 

1 Part of the material of this lecture has been used in an article of The Christian 
Mews Letter } 1 948. 



2 TECHNIC^ [LECT. 

is, the creation and use of artificial tools serving the life of man, 
has increasingly distinguished man's life from that of the 
animal, and imprinted upon it a specifically human character. 
The history of technics from its beginning to, say, ths time of 
James Watt, is characterised by an almost unbroken, more or 
less equable and, therefore, quite unobtrusive progress. Step 
by step man makes headway in solving the task which he recog- 
nises as his own, to subdue nature by his technical inventions. 

We distinguish the first epochs of human history by their 
technical character, speaking of the stone age, the bronze age 
and the iron age, where an almost unnoticeable transition from 
one to the other makes the distinction difficult. The same is 
true of what we call historical man, as we find^him first in the 
Delta of the Nile, in Mesopotamia, in the great valleys of China 
and of India, where the history of civilisation has its origin. 
Everywhere the development of technics is the hardly percept- 
ible and therefore often forgotten basis of political, social and 
cultural change. Nowhere does this technical evolution assume 
a revolutionary aspect, never does it appear as a break with the 
past. All epochs and all nations in history are equally technical 
and therefore none is so in an outstanding sense. That is true 
also of Western history as it first appears as a characteristic 
unity in the Roman Empire ; it is true of the Middle Ages and 
up to the beginning of the 18th century ; but at that moment it 
is as if this underground current suddenly broke through the 
surface. The curve of development which hitherto had been a 
continuously and almost imperceptibly rising straight line, 
abruptly takes the form of a parabola becoming steeper and 
steeper. Technology begins to become a great revolutionary 
power and within the last few decades it has taken the lead in the 
life of the Western nations, and even of the wffole world. It has 
become the dominating factor of modern civilisation. The 
changes which technology has wrought in the last two centuries 
are beyond all comparison with those in previous ages. That 
is why our epoch is called the age of technics, and why the pro- 
blem of technology, unknown to previous epochs, has suddenly 
become the most urgent problem of all. 



i] ne| problems 3 

Why is this so? We might answer this question first by- 
pointing to tjie tempo of technical inventions and the changes 
created by them. The mad speed of technical progress makes 
mankincf breathless; with one invention pressing fast on 
another, man cannot get any rest. The growth of technics is 
out of proportion to the progress made in other departments of 
life, and puts to shame all attempts of society to adapt itself to 
the technical change in order to make it useful and beneficent. 
It is like what happens when a youth suddenly begins to grow 
at a great pace. His spiritual development cannot keep pace 
with his bodily growth and therefore there are disturbances. 



TECHNlCALEVO!£riON_ 



YEARS OF HISTORY 4000 3000 2000 I0OO f~ 1000 1800 

There is a disproportion between bodily and spiritual growth, 
the one taking place at the cost of the other. This comparison, 
with its emphasis on the time-aspect of technical evolution, is 
certainly legitimate. It is true that technical evolution and 
change acquired such a speed that the balance of power within 
society was distuned and that the social changes, which would 
have been necessary to adapt life to them, could not be made 
adequately. We might say that the mushroom growth of giant 
cities, with their apparent poverty of structure and their pro- 
duction of a mass-society and mass-psychology, was a kind of 
surprise-effect produced by lack of time for adaptation. In a 
similar way, one can attribute the preponderance of technical 
interest in our generation to this speedy development of technics. 



4 TECHNICS [LECT. 

But such an analysis remains wholly on the surface. More 
than that: it falsifies the picture of real history by making the 
cause the effect and the effect the cause. This idea of social 
adaptation lagging behind technical progress rather hides than 
reveals the truth. It is not technics which has created the 
modern man, but it is the modern man who has created technics. 
The technical man existed before technics. Take as an example 
the jnost famous novel hero of the age immediately preceding 
the technical revolution, Robinson Crusoe. Compare Robinson 
Crusoe with his colleague in suffering, Ulysses. How differently 
they face their identical lot of being cast by shipwreck on a 
solitary island! There is not much difference, technically, 
between Robinson Crusoe and Odysseus. Perhaps the most 
important difference is that Defoe's hero, in distinction from 
Homer's, has and uses gunpowder. But the main difference is 
this, and this is exactly what Defoe wants to show : how Crusoe 
masters technically his hopeless condition. This is the inspir- 
ing idea which has made the book a favourite of youth: the 
idea of the man who helps himself out of the difficulties, the 
man who — ingenious in quite another sense than Ulysses — is 
capable of subduing hostile nature step by step. 

Behind the technical evolution of the last two hundred years 
there is a much deeper spiritual process, with which the first part 
of these lectures has dealt. This process begins with the Renais- 
sance, leading on to the Enlightenment, and beyond it to the 
radically positivist secularised man of to-day. Modern technics 
is the product of the man who wants to redeem himself by rising 
above nature, who wants to gather life into his hand, who wants 
to owe his existence to nobody but himself, who wants to create 
a world after his own image, an artificial worlc^ which is entirely 
his creation. Behind the terrifying, crazy tempo of technical 
evolution, there is all the insatiability of secularised man 
who, not believing in God or eternal life, wants to snatch as 
much of this world within his lifetime as he can. Modern 
technics is, to put it crudely, the expression of the world-voracity 
of modern man, and the tempo of its development is the expres- 
sion of his inward unrest, the disquiet of the man who is destined 



i] TRANSCENDING NATURE 5 

for God's eternity, but has himself rejected this destiny. The 
hypertrophy of technical interest, resulting in a hyperdynamism 
of technical evolution, is the necessary consequence of man's 
abandonment to the world of things, which follows his 
emancipation from God. 

Let us return for a moment to those quiet periods which 
nobody would call technical, though even then technics had 
reached a high measure of development and was incessantly 
progressive. What do we mean by " technics "? In th<? first 
place, domination over nature, emancipation from its hazards 
by intensifying and multiplying the functions of bodily organs. 
The hammer and the crane are the fortified fist and the pro- 
longed arm, the car is the improved foot, and so on. The whole 
of technics is a continuation of what nature has given to man as 
his particular character: upright walk. That is why technics 
is, as such, a task given to man by the Creator, that Creator who 
gave man the upright spine and thereby the freedom of the use 
of his hands and the eye directed to infinitude. God wants man 
to use his intelligence in order to rise above nature and " subdue 
the earth This phrase is found on the first page of the Bible. 
It immediately follows that other phrase in which the specific 
nature and destiny of man is expressed : " and God created man 
in His own image It is not by chance that the second pre- 
cedes the first. The task of subduing the earth follows from the 
the first. The task of subduing the earth follows from the 
nature and the destiny given to man by the Creator. It is most 
likely that the author of this first chapter of Genesis was think- 
ing of the upright walk of man, but this physical presupposition 
of his superiority is the expression of a deeper reason for superi- 
ority. Man is called to transcend nature, because he is called to 
be godlike. Technics is only one of the forms of nature-trans- 
cendence, but it is that which presupposes the others, higher 
civilisation and spiritual life. 

So long as man does not use artificial means, he remains 
dependent on what nature gives, here and now. That is, he 
necessarily remains on a low, more or less animal, level of devel- 
opment. He is completely at the mercy of natural hazard and 



6 TECHNICSjj [LECT. 

tied to the moment; he cannot look into the future, he cannot 
shape his life, he must live it as nature gives it. By jhe invention 
of artificial tools, man emancipates himself to a certain degree 
from the dictates of nature. The technics* of housebuilSing and 
agriculture make him independent of what nature gives at each 
particular time and place. With a roof over his head and four 
walls around him, he can defy the weather and live where he 
chooses. By agriculture he dictates to the earth what to pro- 
duce for him and to produce it in such a measure that he can 
store up enough for the future. He makes water or wind 
drive his mill He captures the wind in his sail and forces it to 
carry him over the seas. The spinning-wheel^ and the loom 
make him independent of the scarce animal-skins for clothing. 
One by one he cuts the thousand ties by which his body and its 
needs are linked to the fortuitous formation and production of 
the ground. The development of crafts of all sorts leads to 
differentiation of human society and to the specialised training 
and development of spiritual capacities ; it leads to exchange, to 
the communal life of the city, to communication between town 
and town, between country and country. The crafts are at the 
same time a preparation for higher arts and, in the form of 
artistic trade, they play their part in aesthetic ennoblement. 

Technical skill can be learned and, therefore, transmitted 
from generation to generation. That is why in this sphere of 
life there is an unambiguous and more or less continuous pro- 
gress. Each generation learns from the one before and adds 
new inventions. In this process of technical education the mind 
is trained for methodical work. The multiplicity of crafts makes 
for a rich differentiation of the spirit. It cannot be denied that 
cities, with their differentiated crafts, are pre-eminently the 
seats and nurseries of higher culture and education. All these 
organic types of technics — if I may so call them — are easily 
forgotten in our age of highly abstract mechanical and there- 
fore inhuman technics. But they belong to the true picture 
and show the close relation between technics and truly human 
civilisation. 

Even in this picture of pre-modern technics, however, there 



i] DEVELOPMENTS AND DANGERS 7 

are traits of* a more sinister quality. Closely related to the tool, 
and often expressed by the same word, is the weapon. The 
development of crafts almost everywhere gives rise to the de- 
velopment of war technics. There are exceptions to this rule, 
one of the most interesting being that of the older China, where 
an almost unique development of crafts did not lead to a parallel 
development of war technics, because war and fighting were 
stigmatised, culturally and morally. Not even the invention 
of gunpowder, which in Europe had such pernicious conse- 
quences, could become dangerous among this peaceful people. 
The moral discredit of war was so deep that gunpowder was 
never allowed to be used for war purposes, and its dangerous 
energy was puffed out in harmless fire-works. But apart from 
this most honourable exception, the development of technics 
generally resulted in increasingly dangerous weapons and wars. 
The Roman technics of roadbuilding was developed primarily 
for military purposes. The technics of shipbuilding created the 
navy, and so on. Still, all this remained within limits which 
prevented technics from being the dominating potential of war. 

Another danger to society resulting from technical develop- 
ment is the formation of social classes. Technical, like military, 
superiority creates differences of property, social privilege and 
power. These differences, however, so far as they were con- 
ditioned by technics, did not become very dangerous in the 
pre-modem ages, because it was not so difficult to acquire tech- 
nical skill and technical means. From all this, we can conclude 
that on the whole the positive, beneficial aspects of technical 
progress by far outweighed the negative or evil ones. In the 
" golden age of the crafts " nobody would have thought of 
technics as a serious danger or even a problem of civilisation. 

All this is suddenly changed with the introduction of machine 
technics. It had a sort of prelude in the invention of gun- 
powder and its application to warfare. The consequences of 
this invention were far-reaching and could give a premonition of 
what further similar leaps in the development might mean. It 
is strange and somehow shameful that Christian Europe did not 
succeed in doing: — perhaps did not even attempt to do — what 



8 TECHNICSJ [LECT. 

had been achieved by the Chinese. At any rate? with gun- 
powder, technics begins to acquire a negative trait pi European 
history. But incomparably more revolutionary was the inven- 
tion of the steam engine and the locomotive, and later on the 
discovery and technical use of electricity and of petrol, the 
invention of light metals and the development of chemistry. 
Now begins the technical age. As we said before, we should not 
look r upon these inventions as the real causes of the technical 
revolution; they had to come, because men wanted them. They 
had to develop at such an unparalleled rate, because men did not 
want to limit their development in any way. Still, once tech- 
nics had become what it is now, its effects upoiy the social and 
spiritual life of mankind are tremendous. 

It has often been said, and it is obviously true, that all the 
technical changes which took place in the life of men from the 
stone age to James Watt are not nearly as great as those since 
James Watt. The life of a farmer or craftsman before the 
invention of the steam engine was not so different from that of 
Jeremiah's time as from that under modern agriculture and 
industry. Machine industry in the broadest sense of the word, 
including transport and communication, has changed not only 
the life of Europe and America, but that of the whole surface of 
the world, in a tempo and in a measure completely unparalleled 
before. 

This technical revolution has its positive as well as its negative 
side. By it man has indeed subdued the earth in a measure 
inconceivable before. By the radio he has eliminated distance 
completely, so far as mental communication is concerned; by 
the aeroplane he has eliminated it almost completely, so far as 
bodily communication is concerned. The techniques of produc- 
tion are capable of nourishing, clothing, housing every inhabitant 
of this earth in more than sufficient degree and with almost 
complete certainty. Hunger and want are no more inevitable. 
That they are still amongst us is entirely conditioned by 
political, social, international power-relations, preventing the 
reasonable use of technical possibilities. Medical and hygienic 
techniques would be sufficient to create everywhere conditions 



i] ADVANCE|NOT " PROGRESS " 9 

of life whic&t would guarantee to a high degree a healthy life 
and development of the child and double the average age of 
man. The invention of cinema and radio, perfecting that of the 
printing-^ress, allows an almost unlimited spreading of cultural 
assets. In a measure then, present day technics places at the 
disposal of man the means which would safeguard a high stan- 
dard of life and give access to cultural advantages to everyone 
capable of understanding and valuing them. Technical man- 
kind has a superabundance of all things needed, and a super- 
abundance of means to transport them wherever they are 
needed. If there were no war, if there were only just and reason- 
able laws, if all men were well-intentioned, technics would 
provide, so it seems, almost a paradise. The technicians can 
claim that it is not their fault if, at this hour more than ever 
before, mankind presents features of the utmost misery and the 
most unworthy conditions. All this is meant by the phrase 
" technical progress ", which up to recent years was used without 
hesitation. It seems as if technics — and particularly modern 
technics — was an indisputable gain for mankind. 

Why is it, then, that nobody at this hour uses that word 
" progress " without hesitation, if at all? Let us be clear that 
there is no such thing as " technics in itself The production 
of a cannon is a technical affair, but at the same time it is the 
expression of a certain political and military will. The pro- 
duction of dangerous narcotics is a matter of chemical industry, 
but it serves purposes which are medically and morally unsound 
and pernicious. Technics, therefore, is never purely technical. 
It always stands in the closest connection with the totality of 
social and cultural life and of man himself. "Technics" is 
an abstraction which does not exist. There are only men 
workin^technically for certain purposes. When modern man 
conceived the idea of redeeming himself and making himself 
master of his life by technics, he did not know or divine that 
such technics would have results of a very different order. 
What, then, are those effects of the technical revolution which 
an increasing majority of modern men abhor? 

Modern technics does not mean merely a fantastic extension 



10 TECHNIC| [LECT. 

of man's power over nature: it also means millions of men 
working underground, uncounted millions of men massed 
together in soulless giant cities ; a proletariat without connection 
with nature, without a native heath or neighbourhood; It means 
asphalt-culture, uniformity and standardisation. It means men 
whom the machine has relieved from thinking and willing, who 
in their turn have to " serve the machine " at a prescribed tempo 
and in a stereotyped manner. It means unbearable noise and 
rusbr, unemployment and insecurity of life, the concentration of 
productive power, wealth and prestige in a few hands or their 
monopolisation by state bureaucracy. It means the destruction 
of noble crafts with their standards of quality and their patriar- 
chal working conditions; it means the transformation of the 
farmer into a specialised technician of agriculture, the rise of an 
office proletariat with infinitely monotonous work. It means 
also the speedy standardisation of all national cultures and the 
extinction of their historical originality. It means universal 
cliche-culture, the same films and musical hits from New York 
to Tokio, from Cape Town to Stockholm, the same illustrated 
magazines all over the world, the same menus, the same dance- 
tunes. It means the increasing domination of quantity over 
quality, not only in production itself but also in the formation 
of social, political and international power. 

Above all, there are two phenomena in very recent times 
which, like devilish monsters, rise from that progressively 
technified mankind : the modern totalitarian state and modern 
technical war industry. It cannot be said that the totalitarian 
state is the necessary product of technics, but its relation to 
technics is obvious. Without modern technics the totalitarian 
state is impossible. And the tendency towards totalitarianism 
lies within technical evolution: mechanisation, centralisation, 
mass-men. Modern war industry, however, is the direct pro- 
duct of modern technics. Let us remember it is not the techni- 
cians that are guilty, but man who has abandoned technics to 
itself, incapable of bridling its development, putting technics 
without hesitation, and, as if driven by necessity, at the service 
of his political power-aims, This war machinery displayed its 



ij . triumpeJ of THE MACHINE II 

terrifying force in the first world war. The second world war 
manifested i^s increased destructive force; but since then there 
has come that last step or leap : the use of atomic energy, which 
means a*sudden increase in the capacity of annihilation without 
analogy in the previous history of technics. Now the develop- 
ment of technical warfare has reached the point where nothing 
is impossible to it. Mankind for the first time faces possible 
universal suicide. 

This is the other, the dark side of the picture. It shows Tiow 
dangerous it is to speak of technics in abstracto. One could 
have known from the history of technics that every technical 
advance does not change merely man's relation to nature, but 
also man's relation to man. Every invention is an increase in 
power, and every increase in power within society is a danger to 
its balance and order. This fact could remain unnoticed so long 
as technical progress could be assimilated socially and ethically. 
It is the tragic fact of modern history that the technical revolu- 
tion took place at a time when mankind was in a process of social 
dissolution and ethical confusion. It was the era of progressive 
secularisation and mass-atheism, when all ethical standards were 
relativised and men became metaphysically and ethically home- 
less. Cause and effect mutually interpenetrate each other. We 
have already seen that modern technics could not have developed 
without a certain spirit of rationalism and secularisation. It is, 
however, equally true that secularised humanity was not socially 
and ethically equal to the technical revolution. Only a society 
which was incapable of subordinating the profit motive to higher 
motives, a society which was ethically, and even aesthetically 
callous and enfeebled, could allow the growth of those soulless, 
ugly, giant cities, with their speculative building and their 
proletarian quarters. Only such a society could watch without 
protest the dissolution of all natural community, and accept as 
inevitable the development of modem war technics. 

In this connection we have to point out grave fault on the part 
of the Christian Church. The Church ought to have been on the 
watch-tower. She ought to have seen what was going on behind 
those beautiful slogans of freedom and progress. The Church 



12 TECHNIC^ [LECT. 

might have been expected to protect men from enslavement and 
from becoming automatons. The Church ought £o have seen 
that in such conditions, which upset all the order of creation, 
the preaching of the Gospel became almost illusory. Is it not 
shameful for the Christian society that Confucian China was 
capable of suppressing the military use of gunpowder, while the 
Christian Church could not prevent, and did not even try to 
prevent, the development of a war machinery incomparably 
more dreadful? 

European industrial history is not altogether devoid of 
indications of what might have happened if modern industry 
had developed within a truly Christian society. I am thinking 
of a certain phase in the industrial development of Great Britain 
and Switzerland. Within a few decades of the invention of the 
steam engine these countries experienced a physical and social 
devastation within the working population which was definitely 
alarming. But then moral and religious forces reacted and 
were called to the defence. By social legislation, by the trade- 
union and co-operative movements, and by something like an 
awakening of social consciousness through prophetic personali- 
ties, much of the damage was repaired in a comparatively short 
time. What had been called technical necessity proved quite 
unnecessary. The technique of fabrication, so often regarded 
as being beyond ethical control, was effectively put under such 
control. Many things remained bad enough, but yet the effect 
of this ethical-social reaction against the technical materialistic 
laissez-faire gives us a faint idea of what could have been avoided 
if society had awakened in time to the ethical dangers of so- 
called progress. 

Nobody can say how far the disease of uncontrolled, unassimi- 
lated technics has progressed already, whether the disease has 
reached* the point where it becomes incurable or not. It is our 
duty, however, to open our eyes to the imminent threat to life 
and to do whatever we can to make technics serve human ends. 

The nature of technics is to place at man's disposal the means 
for certain purposes. Of course, the production and use of 
technical means is in itself a purpose, but it is never a Selbst- 



ij MEA'ffS AND ENDS 13 

zweck, an ultimate purpose. It is essential to the health of a 
society that this order of ends and means should be known and 
recognised, so that technics as the sum of means is subordinated 
to man's life. Where the means become more important than 
the end, where technics becomes autonomous, a social disease 
develops, which is analogous to cancer: autonomous growths, 
not useful but injurious to the organism, which develop in- 
dependently of the organic centre and finally destroy the 
organism. When, for instance, a country rejoices over the 
growth of a city of millions of inhabitants, this is as stupid as if 
someone were to rejoice over the growth of a cancer. Giant 
cities are merely symptoms, but they are obvious symptoms of 
autonomous technical growth which finally leads to destruction. 

The positive meaning of a human civilisation depends on this 
subordination of means to ends. The reversal of this order, 
therefore, results in civilisation becoming inhuman and finally 
perverted. For this reversal of the order of ends and means, 
which produces a demonic autonomy of technics, secularisa- 
tion is more to blame than technics. It is because the world 
and its goods become to men more important than God, eternal 
life and love, that men throw themselves into the production of 
material goods with that passion of which the human soul, 
destined for infinitude, is capable. Technics was merely the 
means by which this insatiable desire for material goods could 
be, or seemed to be, stilled, because technics is capable of un- 
limited development. Once brought into action, this process of 
unlimited increase and expansion could no longer be controlled. 
The machine invented by man began to control man's will; 
whether he liked it or not he had to obey the logic of technical 
development. I4 was exactly as in Goethe's symbolic ballad, 
Der Zauberlehrling, about the spying apprentice who had found 
out his wizard master's magic word which summoned obedient 
spirits to his service. For a while he revelled in the service of 
the water-carrying spirits; but before long he became afraid, 
because the spirits could no longer be controlled, so that by their 
very service the poor apprentice was in peril of being drowned — 
Die ich rief, die Geister, werd ich nun nicht los — a catastrophe 



14 TECHNIC{ [LECT. 

from which the master's intervention saved him. *This is very- 
like our situation, Man has learned to control tfce immeasur- 
able powers of nature. Modern man dominates nature to a 
degree unthinkable in previous ages. But whilst man controls 
nature by technics he no longer controls his own technics, but 
is more and more dominated by it and threatened with 
catastrophe. 

Last century saw the climax of technical enthusiasm and of 
belief in progress by technics. It was then that people hoped 
technics would relieve man of all impediments and troubles 
connected with his body. " Our saviour is the machine ran 
a sentence in a German newspaper. This enthusiasm for 
technics can still take hold of peoples whose technical develop- 
ment has lagged behind that of Western Europe. It can de- 
velop the more where the ground is prepared by secularist 
thinking which recognises only earthly and material goods. In 
Western Europe, however, this enthusiasm has been followed by 
disillusionment, deep despondency and fear. The first part of 
the story of the Zauberlehrling is finished. The second part is 
in full process and, since the invention of the atomic bomb, is 
approaching its climax. 

Such disillusionment and despair might bring about a real 
turn of the pendulum in the right direction, but only if man is 
capable of understanding something of the deeper causes of this 
fatal, automatic development of technics, if he comes to see the 
false order of means and ends — that is, secularisation, loss of 
faith in God and in eternal values — as the root of the whole 
matter. All other proposals to make technics subservient again 
to human ends, and all attempts to heal the damage to social 
and personal life produced by the technical revolution, are mere 
palliatives. I do not mean that they are worthless, they may 
even be necessary, as the treatment of symptoms — such as 
fighting the fever — is often necessary until more radical therapy 
can begin. But unless there is a basic conversion, technics will 
develop as before, and the tempo of its development will not 
decrease but increase, because nowadays men not only make 
inventions but have found the technique of making inventions. 



ij THE CHRISTIAN ANSWER 15 

For this reason, all corrections coming from outside always come 
too late. The crazy tempo of technical revolution can only be 
reduced to a degree which is socially and personally supportable, 
if the whole scale of values of European nations can be changed. 
As long as material values indisputably take the first place, no 
change for the better is to be expected. 

The perversion of the order of means and ends was caused by 
the decay of the consciousness of personality. And this in its 
turn was the consequence of the decay of Christian faith. In 
our time many have come to see, and are ready to admit, that 
moral values ought to be put in the first place. This insight is 
good, but not sufficient. Mere ethics has never displayed real 
dynamic. You cannot cure a demon-ridden technical world 
with moral postulates. In contrast to mere ethics and morality, 
Christian faith has the dynamic of passion, of surrender and 
sacrifice; it is capable of turning men to the eternal end, of 
unmasking demonic sin and thereby banning it, which no 
enlightened education is capable of doing. 

Technics in itself is no problem for the Christian man. As 
long as technics is subordinate to human will, and human will 
is obedient to the divine will, technics is neutral, and as a means 
of goodwill is itself good. From the Christian point of view, 
there is no reason to condemn the machine and to return to the 
spinning-wheel. Even the use of atomic energy is not in itself 
harmful or bad. But we can hardly avoid the question whether 
technical evolution has not already passed the limits within 
which it is controllable by feeble, mortal men. This question 
cannot be theoretically decided. It is a question of the real 
dynamic. For us the only important question is whether man- 
kind is ready, 03^ may become ready, to perform that inward 
right-about-turn which alone will correct the fatal perversion of 
the order of means and ends. 



II 



SCIENCE 

IF we are to ask what is the most characteristic feature of our 
epoch, we might wonder whether it is science or technics 
which gives the distinguishing mark to our time. "Whilst 
to-day there is an obvious dependence between science and 
technics which makes the latter appear as allied science, it 
should be clear from the start that the unprecedented revolu- 
tionary development of technics in the middle of the iSth 
century had very little to do with science. Technics does not 
have its roots and origin in science, neither is it the scientific 
spirit which gave modern technics its incomparable dynamism. 
Technics springs from the will to dominate nature and to extend 
the power of man. If we are aware of this character of technics, 
it may become very doubtful whether it will be science or tech- 
nics that will win the race that is taking place between the two 
in our time. It does not seem altogether impossible, or even 
improbable, that science may come more and more under the 
domination of technics, which is to say that the independent 
quest for truth may be transformed into a quest for the useful, 
as has already happened in countries where technocracy has 
become the state religion. 

Whilst technics has been in existence in all times and in all 
countries — since man cannot but prove himself as homo faber — 
science is a late-comer in human history; and yhilst all civilised 
nations of olden times reached a high standard of technics, there 
are only a few of them that have produced science. Technics 
originates from the necessities of life ; it is, so to say, vitality in 
the realm of intellect. Science, however, in its essence is a 
decidedly non-pragmatic, " disinterested 99 activity, and for that 
reason much more spiritual than technics. It originates from 
the will to know the truth. A certain amount of suspicion is 



THE, SYNOPTIC VIEW 17 

aroused whep, in a particular epoch, natural science holds the 
field unchallenged by any competition; for this may be an 
index that the interest in truth is already displaced, or at least 
biassed, *by the technical will to dominate nature. What 
legitimises Greek science so unequivocally, and proves its 
nature as a pure science, is, first, the almost complete 
absence of any attempt to apply scientific results technically; 
and in the second place, the astounding parallelism in the 
development of the Geisteswissenschaften alongside of natural 
science. In this sense, the Renaissance may be called a true 
rebirth of the classical scientific spirit. In spite of a simultaneous 
sudden growth^of technical interest, the Renaissance scientists 
were moved by a pure will and a magnificent passion for know- 
ledge of the truth; and some of this purely scientific impulse 
was preserved until quite recent times. Again, this is proved by 
that astonishing parallelism in the development of the Geistes- 
wissenschaften alongside, and in competition with, natural 
science. 

This may be the right moment to draw attention to a peculiar 
linguistic fact which is not without importance from the point 
of view of spiritual history. Neither the French nor the English 
have a common word including both natural science and 
Geisteswissenschaften. History, literature and linguistics do 
not come under the heading of sciences but under that of arts 
or letters. Psychology and sociology are classed with philo- 
sophy, and jurisprudence stands by itself. The German mind 
has had the courage to make the concept of science cover all 
these fields of investigation, evidently because that which is 
common to all of them — the quest for truth — has been felt to be 
more important jhan the differences. This synthetic or synop- 
tic view includes both obligation and danger: obligation to 
scientific rigidity and objectivity, and the danger of a false 
application of the categories of natural science within the field 
of Geisteswissenschaften. In itself however, this synthetic con- 
cept of sciences is a precious heritage of the best Greek scientific 
spirit and an invaluable pointer in the direction of pure science, 
which does not " squint " after practical use — a heritage which 



l8 SCIENCE [LECT, 

in the epoch of technics (when science is in danger of being 
completely dominated by usefulness) cannot be preserved too 
jealously. 

Science takes its orders from truth ; that is its deep, you may 
even say, its religious pathos and ethos. It is not by mere chance 
that in the period of positivist philosophy an attempt has been 
made to divert science from this orientation to truth and to dis- 
credit the very concept of truth. Even in the sphere of pure 
science — physics and even mathematics — the idea of usefulness 
or expediency was substituted for that of truth. The laws 
found by physics were no longer " true " but merely " expedi- 
ent" formulations. It is one of the most gratifying develop- 
ments within this most revolutionary science of our days that 
this compromise with the pragmatic mind of the time has been 
shaken off, and so the temptation to betray the purity of the 
scientific mind has been overcome. Science has decided to 
remain in the service of truth and not to exchange truth for 
expediency. This decision must have the most far-reaching 
consequences. 

Our era, however, has made us familiar with even more 
dangerous possibilities. The dynamic heir of positivist philo- 
sophy, the totalitarian state, has taken hold of science and 
succeeded in making it serviceable to its own purposes : science 
has to take its orders from political power. It has to start from 
its ideological presuppositions and has to prove that they are 
correct. Whether these are the racial philosophy of the Herren- 
volk, or the Marxian doctrine, makes no difference. In both 
cases it means the prostitution of science, which" in the long run 
would mean its end. For a science robbed of its freedom, a 
science to which certain methods, axioms an& results are pre- 
scribed, has ceased to be science ; it is a mere caricature of science. 
The versatility, however, which so many scientists showed in 
letting themselves be won over for this new course, shows more 
clearly than anything else that science has its ethical pre- 
suppositions without which it degenerates. It is dangerous to 
speak of science in the abstract. There is no science, there 
are only men who do scientific work. Science therefore is a 



Il] SCIENCE AND TRUTH ig 

part of human life. That is why science has its ethical pre- 
suppositions.* 

Truth j:s a severe and jealous mistress. She suffers no squinting 
to the left or to the right, she demands unconditional faithful- 
ness. There is a scientific discipline which is much more a 
matter of character than of intelligence, there is a scientific con- 
scientiousness for which the control of others is a poor substitute. 
Maybe a scoundrel of genius might achieve important scientific 
results, but he will do so only because he fits in with a structure 
of methods, standards, checks and tests which are produced and 
applied by a multitude of other scientists who are no scoundrels. 
It is true that personal ambition has played, again and again, an 
important role within the scientific process. But, where it is 
not controlled and checked by the capability and willingness to 
sacrifice personal prestige for the sake of truth, it has proved a 
severe hindrance to scientific progress. On the other hand, one 
of the most awe-inspiring traits of the true scientist is his will- 
ingness to acknowledge as erroneous what hitherto he has 
maintained as true, the willingness to subordinate personal fame 
to objectivity. Whilst it is true that ambition is a powerful 
stimulus of indefatigable research, the greatest achievements of 
science do not spring from ambition. They are the result of a 
genuine passion for truth. Again, the attempt has been made 
to substitute for this passion for truth mere curiosity. Cer- 
tainly, curiosity is an important motive within the field of science. 
But taken by itself it is not sufficient to explain all the sacrifices, 
self-discipline and persistence which alone produce the great 
scientific achievements. Likewise it is impossible to explain in 
terms of egoistic motives the mutual trust between scientists 
which present-day scientific organisation makes necessary. Only 
the one who feels himself pledged to truth, is himself capable of 
trusting his fellow scientists, and he alone will prove capable of 
attaining the highest measure of scientific productivity. With- 
out this practical idealism, without the genuine love and 
reverence of truth, science is doomed to sterility, 

In our days this deepest spring of the scientific spirit is hidden 
by an immense scientific mass-organisation. Thousands of 



20 SCIENCE [LECT, 

researchers are combined within a colossal plan of ^co-operation 
and division of labour, for the purpose of developing our know- 
ledge of nuclear processes. It is obvious that only a minority 
within these thousands are inspired by a genuine scientific ethos. 
The whole thing looks like an enormous business which the 
individual worker might easily exchange for another one. What 
is true of this specific section of physics is true to a certain extent 
of other branches of science. Organisation seems to take the 
lead. But, if you look more closely, you can easily observe that 
even this enormous " big business " within science is unthinkable 
without scientific ethos. You simply have to imagine that the 
majority of those taking part in these organisations are moti- 
vated by mere egoism, and devoid of all truthfulness and con- 
scientiousness, to see the complete impossibility, in such 
conditions, of fruitful co-operation towards one end. Further- 
more, it remains true even now : Wenn Konige bauen, haben die 
Karmer zu tun, x i.e. it is the great individual scientist and not 
the organisation which does the pioneer work. After all, science 
remains the domain of the great solitary truth-seekers who, 
like Kepler, Galileo and Newton, are moved and inspired by a 
sacred reverence for truth. 

It was St. Augustine who made the first attempt to relate the 
idealism of truth to the Christian idea of God. From the point 
of view of a genuine Biblical theology, Augustine's system 
may not be altogether sound, being a synthesis of neoplatonic, 
pantheistic speculation with revealed God-knowledge. His basic 
idea, however, that the God of revelation is the origin of all truth 
had to be accepted even by Biblicists like Luther and Calvin. 
Whoever says " Truth says " God It is the common con- 
viction and tenet of all Christian theology thatchere is no other 
truth — whatever its content — than truth in God. Why is this 
so? 

The first affirmation of the Christian creed is : "I believe in 
God the Father Almighty, Maker of Heaven and Earth True, 
this first sentence, like the rest of the Christian creed, is spoken on 
the basis of God's revelation in history, in Jesus Christ. The 
1 When Kings build — carters must work. 



n] god's immanence 21 

source of thi| knowledge of the Creator is the same as the source 
of the knowledge of God the Saviour. The first part of the Chris- 
tian creed is not a sentence of natural theology. The Christian 
knows the Creator primarily not from creation but from His 
Word. However, it is the specific character of this first part of 
the creed that its content includes objects of our natural know- 
ledge — Heaven and Earth — which as such are also objects of 
scientific investigation. God has created that nature, the fo/ms 
and laws of which Natural Science investigates. He has created 
that man, body and soul, who is the common object of Natural 
Science and Geisteswissenschaften. He has created men and 
world in such away that man is able by his God-given reason to 
know the world — and it is his God-given destiny to know it. 
Moreover, God has created the world and is immanent and 
present in it in such a way that man, in knowing the world, 
cannot but know something of God's power and wisdom. Know- 
ledge of whatever kind, if only it is true knowledge, is therefore 
never something merely natural and worldly; being the act in 
which something God made is grasped according to divine 
destiny, it is in itself something holy, sacred. In so far as true 
knowledge exists, it is always at the same time natural and 
supernatural. 

That is, from the point of view of faith, the reason why know- 
ledge of truth, even the search for truth, has in itself that deep 
"pathos and ethos" which we find present in all genuine 
scientific research, and which we find, before all, a dominant 
motive with the pioneers of science. Therefore all science could 
be, and ought to be, a divine service, a reverent following the 
traces — lineamenta, as Calvin says — of God's creation. Behind 
the postulate of*scientific objectivity we find nothing less than 
awe in the face of God's order. What the scientist discovers are 
materialisations of God's thought and will. Man is not mistaken 
but supremely right if he feels science to be a high, divine 
vocation closely linked up with his human dignity, a sacred 
cause which requires surrender, loyalty and obedience, a duty 
which is laid upon him and which he cannot forsake arbitrarily. 

If we understand science in this fashion there can be no 



22 SCIENCE [LECT. 

conflict with faith. It is the same God who has created this world 
which we penetrate by our scientific endeavours, arid who reveals 
Himself in history. The revelation of God in His V^oxd does 
not make scientific research unnecessary or unlawful. The 
Word of God in Scripture is no divine text-book of astronomy 
or anthropology. God's revelation in His Word is given to us 
by men who lived in the pre-scientific ideas of their time. On 
the a other hand, no science can ever hope to give us what God 
reveals in His Word, because the world can never disclose the 
secret of God's gracious Will, forgiving man his sin and pro- 
mising him eternal life. Science and faith are on different 
planes, perhaps we may say on planes standing vertically at right 
angles to one another, and having therefore merely a common 
intersecting line. The revelation in Christ takes place in that 
world which science investigates, but this revelation cannot 
become an object of science. Therefore it is equally stupid not 
to believe in God for scientific reasons and to oppose science for 
reasons of faith. The battle between Christian theology and 
science, which has aroused so much bad feeling between the two, 
has proved to be a mutual misunderstanding, caused by an over- 
stepping of limits, partly from the side of faith, partly from that 
of science. In principle this problem does not exist any longer, 
though in practice it may never cease to bother us. 

But the world in which we live and which we know is not 
simply God's creation, because we ourselves are not simply the 
men whom God created. Between God's creation and ourselves 
lies a gulf, a catastrophe which Christian faith calls the fall of 
man into sin. Even the scientist within his own sphere experi- 
ences the repercussions of this catastrophe. He does so in his 
ever-repeated experience that the scientific rmn accomplishes 
his service of truth less faithfully and reliably than he ought to, 
that he is often led by motives which are unfavourable to the 
knowledge of truth. Egoism, vanity, lust for power, partisan- 
ship of all kinds, are well known to have played an important 
role in scientific life. But the effects of sin within the scientific 
world are even deeper, so that they are hidden from moral 
commonsense. Man as a sinner is estranged from God, and so 



Il] SCIENCE AND SIN 23 

his sense of truth is poisoned at its very root In the same place 
where St. Pai|f speaks of God's revelation in His created Work, he 
also lays his finger on this sore spot, that man in his sinful 
illusions tonfounds creation and Creator. He calls God what is 
not God. He absolutises what is not absolute. Again — and this 
is the aspect which is most important in the history of science — 
he simply forgets God and ignores the divine truth. All these 
possibilities, of which we have merely sketched an outline, 
have been realised in scientific progress and played fatal rofes : 
false absolutes — we might call them the pseudo-scientific myths 
— relativism, the illusion of positivism, that is, independence of 
all metaphysics^ From the Christian point of view all these are 
equally manifestations of the one deep perversion of the mind 
which must pervert and deflect the course of science. 

With the last remarks we touch upon the problem which the 
German calls scientific Voraussetzungslosigkeit, i.e. the postulate 
that the scientist must have no presuppositions. If by that we 
mean that scientific investigation must not be tied to any pre- 
conceived results but has to be completely open to the facts, what- 
ever the facts may be, this postulate is identical with the idea 
of scientific inquiry as such. It is the postulate that science 
takes its orders from truth. But if by that postulate we mean 
to say that the scientist, in order to be a true scientist, must not 
have religious beliefs, such an axiom proves to be a mere pre- 
judice which has nothing to do with science. This kind of 
Voraussetzungslosigkeit, just as the similar idea of indifference 
to value, is neither possible nor desirable. 

For the scientist it is no gain but a loss if he does not believe 
in truth, the quest for which is a sacred service. That prac- 
tical idealism which makes the scientist capable of sacrifice, 
that deep religious " pathos and ethos " which, as we have seen, 
is the characteristic of the greatest pioneers of science, is a potent 
motive and a directing force. It is the best, and perhaps the 
only sufficient, guarantee for an unconditional, genuine search 
for truth, and therefore for true scientific progress. Let us 
remember how, in the era of positivist philosophy, the substitu- 
tion of utility for the idea of truth has endangered scientific 



24 SCIENCE [LECT. 

activity. Much more do we see, in our era of technocracy and 
totalitarianism, how destructive the effect of utilitarianism and 
the loss of scientific ethos must be. There is, however, no truer, 
no purer " pathos and ethos 99 than the one which flows 6ut of the 
Christian idea of God. Only those who cannot grasp the pro- 
found difference between faith-knowledge and scientific know- 
ledge will believe that Christian faith anticipates replies to 
scientific questions and thereby destroys the necessary openness 
of file scientific mind. 

But the positive contribution of faith to science is more than 
that. On closer inspection that metaphysical Voraussetzungs- 
losigkeit or " neutrality " or " indifference whi^h the positivist 
postulates, is no real possibility. He who does not believe as a 
Christian cannot help believing in something. That assumed 
neutrality proves to be a phantom, something which neither is 
nor can be. The metaphysical dimension of the mind never 
remains empty, but must always have a content. If it is not the 
Christian faith, then it is some kind of alternative metaphysics 
which is much more dangerous for science, being unconscious. 
Metaphysical neutrality simply does not exist, because neutrality 
in itself is a kind of sceptical metaphysics. 

It is not surprising, then, that during the last centuries, when 
rationalistic philosophy and materialism took hold of the 
Western mind, we see within the field of science the appearance 
of certain axioms which seemed to be self-evident, but which 
were nothing but hidden, unconscious metaphysics: partly 
idealistic, partly materialistic. Such an axiom was the pan- 
causalism of the 18th century, the idea of Laplace, of a universal 
world-mechanics. A similar axiom took hold of the 19th cen- 
tury science: pan-evolutionism, i.e. the extension of the 
Darwinian principle of selection to the totality of phenomena, 
particularly to history. In general, we see a tendency to apply 
certain categories, which have proved helpful and even necessary 
in certain areas of science, to others by the sheer impetus of a 
monistic conception of Truth and Being. Wherever Christian 
faith was alive, these tendencies were powerfully resisted, but 
this was the exception, the movement of the time going in the 



Il] THE ERROR OF THE "OPEN MIND " 25 

opposite direction. At no time has this pseudo-scientific, 
monistic t^pdency dominated in a more dictatorial and 
uncritical way than in the era of positivist philosophy under 
the disguise of the slogan of metaphysical neutrality. What 
presented itself as metaphysical neutrality was, as a matter of 
fact, blunt naturalism, not to say stupid materialism: a pre- 
conceived axiom of the unity and uniformity of all phenomena. 
Of course this is metaphysics, metaphysics of the worst type. 
Instead of a true openness of mind not prejudicing the character 
of Being, we have here a metaphysical dogma of the uniformity 
of all Being, which proved to be genuinely harmful in the field of 
Geisteswissenschaften and contributed no little to the sad con- 
dition of the present world. I only mention a naturalistic 
sociology which abolished the notion of justice and introduced, 
instead, the principle of the survival of the fittest. 

The postulate of the Voraussetzungslosigkeit proves to be mis- 
leading also from the point of view of epistemology. No science 
can work without Voraussetzungen (in Greek: hypothesis). 
Science gets answers only if it asks questions, and questions are 
alternative presuppositions. True scientific openness of mind 
does not consist in having no presuppositions but in having 
intuitively the right presuppositions in the form of questions or 
hypothetical answers. Only where the right questions are 
asked, that is, where the right hypotheses are intuitively intro- 
duced into the field of research, is new knowledge gained. 
Natural Science failed to progress as long as it was dominated by 
Aristotelian categories taken from the realm of man. On the 
other hand, where man and his history are subjected to the 
categories of Natural Science the results will be meagre, and in 
part pseudo-scientific. It so happens that man is different from 
his surrounding nature. Similarly, whoever were to use merely 
mechanical presuppositions in his study of organic life, would 
miss his object, because it so happens that the mechanical and 
the organic are different. Whoever works with a preconceived 
dogma of the uniformity of Being cannot but do wrong to some 
part of reality. 

If once the false metaphysics, lying at the root of this monistic 



26 SCIENCE [LECT. 

conception and the axiom of metaphysical neutrality, is seen as 
erroneous, the road is open for a further insight w|dch throws a 
new light on the importance of Christian faith for true science. 
I am speaking of the knowledge of man, who is evidently a very 
specific, unique object of knowledge. He is unique for the 
reason that he is at the same time both the object and the subject 
of that knowledge, being the subject of all knowledge and science. 
Man is not merely one amongst the objects, because all know- 
ledge, everything which we know of the world and nature, has its 
seat within man's mind. If I am not mistaken, it is exactly the 
most objective of all sciences — mathematical physics — which has 
reached a point where. this indissoluble connection of subject 
and object has become evident in an overwhelming manner. 
Amongst all objects, man is the one who is always both object 
and subject at the same time. That is the deeper reason why 
the so-called Geisteswissenschaften, since they have to do with 
human history and the products of the human mind, have a 
structure so different from Natural Science that, as we have seen, 
Frenchmen and Englishmen prefer not to call them sciences. 

The more deeply we penetrate into the being of man, the more 
clearly does it appear that the specifically human — that which is 
his alone — is the fact that he transcends himself. What we call 
culture is a product of man's self-transcendence. So is science. 
Man wants to know the truth; that truth reveals itself to him 
only in parts, in fragments, and therefore he must remain critical 
with regard to the results of his investigations; he must be ready 
to correct them. The mainspring of all this self-criticism is his 
passion for absolute truth; not a single fragment of knowledge 
is gained, as Planck has reminded us, if absolute truth is not 
aimed at. All science lives on this perspective of absolute truth. 
It is by this perspective that we can say : this is merely relatively 
true. Whoever says " relative must first have said " absolute M . 
This is the self-transcendence of man as it manifests itself in 
science. 

Now, the most important manifestation of this self-transcend- 
ence is that act by which man transcends not only all he knows, 
but his very being, in subjecting himself to the judgment of 



n] man's self-transcendence 27 

ultimate truth. That he does this is one thing, how he does it 
is another. "\|Tiich is that Truth to which he subjects himself 
in the totality of his being? This question, inevitable as it is, 
carries us beyond the range of mere knowledge into the sphere of 
faith. It cannot be answered without personal decision. The 
Christian believer does this in a manner different from the rest. 
The truth to which he subjects himself and by which he feels 
himself judged is unique in two features : in the radical nature 
of this judgment and in its thoroughly personal character. The 
believer knows that only by knowing God truly, does he know 
himself truly. That is why the Christian believer has a know- 
ledge of himself different from all the others : he knows himself 
as a creature which is responsible to the Creator, and which at 
the same time lives in contradiction to his God-given destiny. 
Furthermore, he knows himself as a creature whose destiny it is 
to live in the Divine Love offered to him in the revelation of 
Divine Truth. 

It is easily understood that the exploration of human history 
and of the specifically human manifestations, such as language, 
culture, state, law and so on, must lead to different results 
according as the explorer uses as his working hypothesis this 
Christian conception of man, or does not use it. Within the 
scientific process he uses this Christian view of man merely as a 
working hypothesis, ready to correct it, if his object makes it 
necessary. But the conflict between him as a believer and as a 
scientist never takes the form of an ultimate alternative, because, 
it so happens that the Christian view of man proves itself to be 
the only realistic one, that is, the only one which stands the test 
of experience and does not falsify the picture of human reality. 
Whilst it is true that the Christian view of man gets its accurate 
form only in the^rocess of critical scientific research, and many 
of the traditional formulations have to be sacrificed, it proves 
itself a key, opening doors which remain closed to any other. 

The Christian conception of man produces also a certain view 
of the place of science within the totality of human existence, 
namely that science, however important, has no legitimate claim 
to the first place. Science knows what is, it does not know what 



28 SCIENCE 

ought to be. Science is a part of human destiny, but it is not 
this destiny itself, simply because it refers to wl$at is and does 
not refer to what ought to be. Science is human, but it is not 
the human. Isolated from the totality of human destiny, or 
put into the first place dominating the rest, it kills the human 
centre, making men inhuman. It destroys personality, respon- 
sibility and love. Science is not bound to have this fatal result; 
it does have this result only if it usurps the first place, which does 
ntft belong to it. 

Speaking in general, science in our day claims more room 
within the totality of human life than it is entitled to. Instead 
of serving, it dominates ; instead of subordinating itself, it wants 
to subordinate the whole of life; that is why it has, in part, 
dehumanising effects. This is not the fault of science, but of 
man misunderstanding the function of science and giving it an 
importance which it should not have. It is not from science 
that we have to learn what is the task of man and what is the 
meaning of his existence. These are questions which lie outside 
the range of science, in the sphere of faith. Science is related to 
truth, but science is not the only way to truth. What science 
can know is a certain aspect of truth. The all-including Truth 
is God, and God is not an object of scientific knowledge. He is 
not an object at all, being the absolute subject, the one who has 
destined us, created relative subjects, for Himself and made us 
responsible to Him. Being the absolute subject, He never can 
be grasped by us. If we know Him, it is because He reveals 
Himself to us. When this happens — when the light of His 
truth enlightens and grasps us — then we begin to understand 
Him as the meaning of human existence and as the source of 
that deep " pathos and ethos " which is the life of genuine 
science. 



Ill 



TRADITION AND RENEWAL 

CERTAINLY nobody would claim that our age is suffering 
from an overemphasis on tradition. Since the struggle 
against the ancien regime, particularly since the French 
Revolution, the western world has undergone a process of dis- 
solution of tradition. The one example of England, however, 
proves that it is not merely the inertia of the forces then released 
which accounts for the continuation of this process. England, 
too, had its revolution, but after its successful accomplishment, 
the life of this island people re-established continuity with the 
previous tradition and never lost it in the following centuries. 
Within the rest of the western world there were always forces 
acting in an anti-traditional sense after the removal of the 
ancien regime. 

The main force was rationalism. Continental Europe and the 
United States have experienced the effect of enlightenment much 
more deeply than Great Britain. Rationalism, the principle of 
enlightenment, is anti-traditional, for tradition does not belong 
to those "clear and perspicuous ideas" in which, since Descartes, 
the enlightened individual believes. The main argument of 
tradition — it was so, therefore it shall remain so — is offensive to 
modern man. What he cannot justify here and now in the light 
of reason does not put him under any obligation. The motive 
force of equality also works in the opposite sense from that of 
tradition. We people of to-day are equal to those who were 
before us. Therefore we have as much right to decide for our- 
selves what shall be and what shall not be, as they had in their 
time. By their reason men are essentially equal and alike. 
That which is unlike is unessential and should not be considered 
as essential. So tradition has no precedence over what seems to 
us better to-day. Tradition is essentially an aristocratic and not a 



30 TRADITION AND RENEWAL [LEGT. 

democratic principle. In a world in which democracy, in the 
sense of equality, has become a kind of religion! tradition can 
neither be kept nor be formed. This is one of the main causes 
of the instability of western society during the* last two 
centuries. 

For tradition, rightly understood, plays the role of a firm 
scaffolding amongst the forces which create and carry the cul- 
tural life. Tradition means continuity, the element of duration 
antl of persistence. The Latin word, tradere, means " to pass 
on " ; those of the older generation pass on to the younger what 
they have received themselves. Tradition is inheritance, first in 
the very banal economic sense. Where there p no passing on 
of material values from father to son and grandson, there tradi- 
tion in a spiritual sense will hardly persist. Culture presupposes 
continuity within its material foundation. Where the State by 
death duties and other taxation destroys this material continuity, 
it will also in the long run destroy the sense of spiritual tradition. 

Tradition is, so to speak, cultural memory, the living preser- 
vation of the past in the present. Therefore tradition and the 
historical sense are closely connected. Where there is no love 
for the past, living tradition becomes impossible. The two merge 
imperceptibly: the passing on of historical memory and the 
passing on of values from the past generation to the coming 
generations. In order to pass on what has been, one must know 
it. Behind both, historical interest in the past and the passing 
on of values from the past, there is the same conception of the 
unity of the generations across the change of time, the solidarity 
between the present and the past. Only where the past is con- 
sidered as ours — as something which belongs to us just as much 
as that which shall be to-morrow — can these two elements 
coexist : reverence for what past generations have done and the 
consciousness of guilt. To acknowledge guilt means to consider 
the past as a living presence. Where tradition and historical 
interest become weak, the consciousness of guilt also becomes 
weak. 

With these reflections we have already touched the Christian 
view of tradition. The principle of tradition is deeply rooted in 



Ill] CHRISTIANITY AND TRADITION 31 

the Christian |Conception of life. The connection with those 
who were before us is guaranteed by the idea that all mankind is 
bound together with solidarity in creation and in sin. All of us 
are one in " Adam We cannot forget that " Adam's " 
creation and destiny are ours. We cannot disconnect ourselves 
from " Adam's " guilt. All mankind has a common inheritance 
of creation and of sin. In the Christian message history is of 
capital importance. It is not surprising, then, that tradition, is 
the very essence of the Christian Church. Paradosis is one of 
the key words of the Bible. To pass on what God has done and 
given to the previous generations is one of the most sacred duties 
of the Old Testament community. The Roman Catholic Church 
is right in affirming the capital importance of tradition. It is 
not on this point that the Reformation broke away from it; 
the break took place on the question whether or not the New 
Testament should be the norm of this tradition. But, in any 
case, the Christian Church lives by the passing on of historical 
revelation. The Church is a living continuity of past revelation, 
across the change of time. 

Because the Church in her very essence is holy tradition, she 
also is the legitimate guardian of all natural and cultural 
tradition. This function she exerted, though imperfectly, in 
that epoch of tremendous break-down, when the Graeco-Roman 
cultural tradition was about to be lost. She performed the 
same function of guardianship throughout the Middle Ages, in 
the Greek Orthodox Churches and in the Churches of the 
Reformation, passing on the cultural inheritance at a time when 
respect for the past was already vanishing. Certainly Christi- 
anity shares the credit for this with the Renaissance Humanism, 
which in a more direct manner restored the continuity with 
antique culture. It is customary to attribute to Renaissance 
Humanism rather than to the Christian Church the chief merit 
of having given classical antiquity its legitimate share of modern 
European civilisation. Upon closer inspection, however, we 
shall see two things : first, that Renaissance Humanism showed 
its strength not outside but inside the Christian stream of life; 
second, that this Humanism fell a prey to rationalism and 



32 TRADITION AND RENEWAL [LECT. 

finally decayed in proportion to its alienation f ror^L the Christian 
tradition. Humanism kept its cultural vigour only where it 
remained in contact with Christianity, for the decisive element 
of tradition, i.e. loyalty to the heritage of the past, does not lie 
within the principle of Humanism as such, but in the Christian 
view of history. 

This apparent paradox may be illustrated by a fact of lan- 
guage. During the whole of the Middle Ages until the end of 
die 17th century, the Latin language was the universal means of 
communication between European nations. Whoever had a 
claim to education spoke Latin. In our present era of Babel-like 
confusion of language we look back upon thi/ time with envy. 
Why is it that this living connection with antiquity was broken? 
There may be many answers to this question, but there is one 
which seems to have more truth than others, namely that the 
Humanists with the Ciceronian Latin of the scholars killed the 
medieval Latin which the Church had made the universal means 
of communication. Had we kept it, we might be capable now 
of breaking the national linguistic barriers, as was the case when 
Englishmen, Frenchmen, Italians and Spaniards followed the 
Latin lectures of the German, Albertus Magnus, at the Sorbonne.. 

Tradition is not merely keeping alive the spiritual heritage of 
the past. Even more important, because more closely connected 
with the personal and social character of man, is the continuity 
of social values, such as custom, law, civil institutions, family 
tradition, public spirit and virtue. We understand best the 
tremendous importance of social rootedness and stability if we 
start from its opposite, as it is represented in a large modern 
industrial city. Already the outward picture of such a modern 
mushroom growth, compared with a city of (Ad cultural tradi- 
tion, is characteristic. One cannot refrain from expressing the 
contrast in terms of " mechanism " and " organism There is 
nothing more ugly, soulless and inhuman on the face of this 
earth than a gigantic mushroom-city built up by the accidental 
conflux of large masses at a place of industrial opportunity. It 
is like a giant city of brick barracks entirely dominated by the 
principle of bare utility, of mere " lodging without any form, 



Ill] NEED OF A COMMON LIFE 33 

without the wiljl to express togetherness and community, without 
any attempt to express outwardly an inward conviction. You 
can " make 99 such a city of barracks, but you cannot " make " a 
city of culture ; it must grow, and grow slowly. What such a city 
of a million lodgings tells you is this : here are masses of men 
whirled together by the blast of economic opportunity, each one 
a detached individual without any connection with the others, 
without anything but the bare necessity of making a living jo 
hold them together. There is no chance for the growth of a 
real community life because there is nothing in common. The 
inhabitants are all alien and indifferent to each other. There is 
no common histof y, there are no common memories, no common 
heritage, no common origin. Next year you may just as well 
live in any other similar city. Such a city has no character 
whatever, no individuality; it cannot rouse any feeling of 
loyalty. How could you love this city? Why should you feel 
tied to it? Why should you feel that you belong to it and that 
you all belong together? Nobody would say with pride : " I am 
of this city. It is my city. I am its citizen 

Such a city, then, is the expression of a life without tradition. 
Tradition is social rootedness, living togetherness, on the basis 
of common history, of family acquaintance through many gene- 
rations. Tradition is for men in general what the house of the 
parents is for the child. As a child cannot develop normally 
without family life, so men cannot become truly human without 
tradition, without growing into the life of past generations. 
Certainly man is created to be an individual personality. This 
is the law of the Creator. But just because it is so difficult to 
become a person, he needs the support of the community, and 
that means rooteciness in, and contact with, generations preced- 
ing us and sharing with us their mature experience. You do 
not place a new-born child in the street, telling him now to look 
after himself. In a way man always remains a child. He never 
becomes independent in an absolute sense. He always lives 
from that which others have learned, thought, experienced and 
created before him. 

Uprootedness does not mean independence. On the contrary, 



34 TRADITION AND RENEWAL [LEGr, 

the uprooted man can never become independent. He is pre- 
destined to become a mass-man, a particle of a collectivist 
mechanism, an object of the totalitarian state. The decay of 
tradition during the last few generations is one of the most im- 
portant presuppositions of totalitarian collectivism. It has 
created the mass-man, just as the deforestation of the Mississippi 
Valley has created the sandy- soil of the " dust bowl which the 
stprms blow into heaps and then disperse. It is not the huge 
size of city populations which creates the mass-man, it is the lack 
of a common tradition. 

It is not modern technics which is the main cause of social 
deracination, but a conception of life which has ceased to value 
tradition, that rationalism which has no relation to the past but 
sees life merely as a series of independent presences. Paradoxi- 
cally, man who has no past has no future either. Man, to whom 
tradition is sacred, plants trees and creates benefits for the next 
generations ; because he has part in the past, he looks prudently 
into the future. The uprooted mass-man cares for neither past 
nor future. He lives — as we say in German — in den Tag 
hinein; he does not save, but spends what he has. He does 
not bother what becomes of his work, he does not love durable 
things, he loves change, and duration seems to him tedious. It 
is only reverence for the past which makes you love things which 
last. That is why our age is so incredibly unstable. The sense 
of stability has been destroyed. The value of duration is dis- 
credited by a philosophy of incessant change. How should one 
who has been taught that only the new is good, and who has 
never been taught the value of old things, love that which 
endures? 

For the Christian, the valuation of tradition^ primarily based 
upon the belief in God's order of creation and preservation. 
Was unset Gott erschaffen hat, das will Er auch erhalten. 1 The 
created order of the family, as an expression of divine will, is the 
foundation of all tradition. The family is based upon fidelity 
and loyalty between successive generations. The divine com- 
mandment "Thou shalt honour thy father and mother" is 

1 What God has created he will maintain. 



the Magna Carta of all true tradition. This commandment, 
on the other ftand, presupposes that the older generation takes 
the responsibility for the coming one. The chain holding 
together the generations and so forming tradition is woven of 
respectful gratitude and far-sighted responsibility. The fifth 
commandment is, however, only part of the divine law. This 
law, standing above the change of time, guarantees stability 
against change. The same law which has bound the old, binds 
the young. That is why it is written on stone tables. It is 
meant to last for ever. Where the sense of the divine law as the 
basic order of life is alive, you need not be concerned about the 
power of tradition. Even within those nations to whom the 
divine law and order of creation were only imperfectly known, 
but who were loyal to what they knew, the continuity of tradi- 
tion was solid and the chain linking the generations proved to 
be unbreakable. The divine order of creation and the divine 
law formulating it are the basis of natural tradition. 

But now tradition, fundamental as it is, is not solely a positive 
value in the life of mankind. Es erben sich Gesetz und Rechte 
wie eine ew'ge Krankheit fort (Goethe). 1 The stable element 
can dominate in such a way that it kills. Life is renewal and 
human life, in particular, is creation of the new. Man is distin- 
guished from animals just by the fact that he creates new things ; 
that he does not repeat the same melody throughout the cen- 
turies, but invents new songs; that he does not reproduce the 
same pattern like the bee and the beaver. The element of 
creativity is inseparable from spirit and culture; it is new know- 
ledge, new invention, the creation of something which has never 
been before. In order to create the new, one has to be independ- 
ent of the old. pne needs courage, love of adventure, to sail into 
the unknown dangers of the open sea. Here is the field for the 
pioneer who is not afraid to stand alone, to swim against the 
stream and to take a course hateful to the mass of those who are 
bound by tradition. 

Nay, is not living tradition in itself renewal? Was Du ererbt 

x Law and rights are handed down from generation to generation l&e a 
never-ending disease. 



r> 



go TRADITION AND RENEWAL [LECT. 

von deinen Vatern hast, erwirb es 3 um es zu besitzen (Goethe). 1 
Living tradition is not merely transmission but a deceiving and 
giving which on both sides is creative. Every live teacher is 
somehow an artist who, by teaching, releases the sleeping powers 
of the pupil, while a live pupil does not merely receive, but by 
appropriating forms something new. When tradition becomes 
mechanical reproduction, it is neither alive nor human. 
Genuine tradition is creative appropriation which in itself 
is ^progressive transformation. Live individuality cannot 
appropriate without giving, stamping with its own stamp. 
Appropriation means reception into the organic whole, which 
in itself is unique. 

The creation of new things is necessary because what has 
been reached up to now is only a step on the long road to a 
distant end. The capacity to transcend himself, which is the 
very essence of man, is founded in the idea of perfection and 
absoluteness, with regard to which every achievement appears 
as a mere approximation which cannot ultimately satisfy. The 
restless reaching out after the new is not grounded merely in a 
desire for change but in this striving for the perfect and absolute 
which dwells in the human mind. The more inexorably each 
achievement is measured by the norm of perfection and absolute- 
ness, the more alive is the spirit. The spirit is thus living in the 
unrest of a "not yet". This is the dynamic of the idea of 
progress. It might appear, then, that the intensity with which 
the idea of progress has moved the modern mind is a sign of the 
spiritual vitality of our age. 

This would really be so if that " not yet " were the true expres- 
sion of our relation to the perfect and absolute. This superficial 
evaluation of our human situation is, however, exactly that false 
optimism which was the reproach of the past century. To see 
our reality from the view-point of " not yet " is an optical illu- 
sion. Not only is our life not yet good, not yet human, but 
rather no more good and no more human. It is not merely 
incomplete with regard to the perfect, but it contradicts it. 
This statement does not apply to all spheres in the same 

1 What thou hast inherited from thy fathers acquire it so as to possess it. 



Ill] THE CHURCH AND TRADITION 37 

way. There are things which are imperfect or incomplete. 
The category of contradiction — or opposition— is meaningless, 
say, in the sphere of technical problems. The first locomotives 
were really imperfect compared with the present ones. In this 
sphere there is unambiguous progress. The same is true, 
although not in the same measure, of scientific knowledge. 
Science proceeds from the imperfect to a more and more perfect 
condition of knowledge. 'However, the category of "not yet" 
becomes most problematic in the moral sphere, and it becomes 
entirely wrong where the moral condition is viewed in connection 
with our God-relation. Our relation to God cannot be said to 
be "not yet" g^od. From the point of view of faith it is 
clearly " no more " good, that is, it is placed in the category of 
opposition or contradiction. Sin is not mere imperfection but 
deviation, opposition to the will of God, even destruction of the 
God-given status. The more man's understanding of himself 
becomes personal, the more the category of " not yet " becomes 
irrelevant. The fact of " opposition " is central, and progress 
is an unsuitable category in the Christian understanding of 
man's relation to God. Where man's true being is understood 
as communion with God, the judgment on our actual being is 
this : loss of communion, separation from God by sin and guilt. 
The only possible solution of the human problem is the restora- 
tion of the destroyed communion by forgiveness and salvation. 

With the message of redemption in Christ and of ultimate 
salvation, a completely new element enters human life which 
also entirely reshapes the relation of tradition and renewal. The 
restoration of God-communion is perfected in Christ. We look 
back upon it as something past. " It is finished ", once and for 
all. The knowledge of this divine achievement is entrusted to 
the Church, that she may pass it on from generation to genera- 
tion. This passing on — this traditio — is her very essence and 
life. Church is tradition. On the other hand, what the Church 
passes on is something perfecdy new, the unheard of novelty of 
divine forgiveness, gratuitous love and the promise of final sal- 
vation and perfection. The content of the Christian message 
and tradition are those things which "eye saw not, and ear 



38 TRADITION AND RENEWAL [lECT. 

heard not — prepared for them that love Him Jesus Christ is 
the " novissimum " of all history which cannot be derived from 
anything preceding, but which also remains the "novissimum" 
throughout all history. He is the end of all history, its trans- 
cendent goal; to believe in Him means also to believe in a new 
heaven and a new earth. "Behold, I make all things new", says 
He, who is the alpha and the omega, the beginning and the end. 

iThat is why Christian faith, wherever it is genuine, is not 
merely a power for progress but a revolutionary force in history. 
Faith in Christ, in the One who started a new history, is at the 
same time renewal of human existence here and now. Christian 
faith is inseparable from new birth, from being a new creature. 
" Wherefore, if any man is in Christ, he is a new creature : the 
old things are passed away; behold, they are become new." 
This newness bursts asunder all continuity of tradition. Such 
novelty is not merely an improvement but a perfect revolution, 
a revolution of thought and will. In the New Testament the 
patterns of continuity are rejected in sharpest antithesis. The 
new man is opposed to the old man in blunt contradiction. In 
a radical right-about-turn man must break with the old and turn 
completely towards the new. Christian existence is radically 
revolutionary, being the expectation of the perfectly new world. 

But what, then, of the necessity for tradition and conserva- 
tion? We have to distinguish between centre and periphery. 
The New Testament faith is radically revolutionary in the centre, 
that is, in its relation to God and to men, but it is not at all 
revolutionary in the periphery. Neither Jesus nor the Apostles 
attack the state or the social order with the intention o£ replacing 
them by another order. Not even such an immoral institution 
as slavery is directly questioned. The revolution takes place at 
first in the personal centre only. This emphatic distinction 
between centre and periphery is such a marked feature of the 
new life in Christ that at first sight the community of early 
Christians might appear to be utterly conservative in the politi- 
cal, social and cultural spheres. If we recall, however, that little 
jewel of the New Testament, St. Paul's letter to Philemon, we see 
that this conservatism is merely apparent. This letter was 



Ill] RENEWAL THROUGH CHRIST 39 

addressed to a member of the Christian Church in Colossse, 
recommending its bearer, a fugitive slave, to his master. Whilst 
St. Paul takes the institution of slavery for granted, he trans- 
forms it from within into a relation of brotherhood. A silent 
revolution takes place in the personal centre and from there 
transforms the social relationship. 

We cannot understand such a relation between centre and 
periphery unless we bear in mind that the renewal through 
Christ is at the same time the restoration of the primeval gdbd 
creation of God. Through Jesus Christ the image of God in 
man, which has been destroyed by sin, is restored. By the silent 
revolution the ejreatureliness of man is not ascetically negated, 
but completed or fulfilled. Nowhere is this more clearly to be 
seen than in the element which is so decisive for tradition: 
marriage and the family. Marriage is not denied but fulfilled 
through Christ by being made a symbol of the unity between 
Christ and His body. In a similar way the institution of the 
family is not dissolved but transformed from within by being 
made a symbol of the paternal filial relation between God and 
man. 

This is to say that the radical revolution within the invisible 
centre creates a silent revolution in the visible periphery, not by 
changing laws, institutions and orders as such, but by inwardly 
transforming them and giving them a new meaning. That is 
why the most revolutionary force of world history manifests 
itself under the disguise of a conservative attitude. It is exactly 
by being so radically revolutionary, that it takes a conservative 
appearance. The Christian knows that all changes which begin 
from without are no real changes. For, after all, it is always 
man who makes the conditions and not the conditions that make 
men. Outward revolutions are therefore at bottom fictitious, 
much ado about nothing. Of course the world does not believe 
this. For the superficial mind, which fails to understand the 
real relation between centre and periphery, the silent revolutions 
always are too slow and not radical enough. It is only by 
becoming a Christian that a true valuation of the really revolu- 
tionary forces is gained; the secularised mind will always 



40 TRADITION AND RENEWAL [LECT. 

overestimate outward appearance and underestimate radical, 
inward change. 

The true revolution, even within the social, political and 
cultural spheres, is always that which takes place within and 
seems to be conservative without. Certainly, there is a danger, 
lest the principle of inwardness become a mere disguise of 
unreality. This danger is, however, inseparable from the life of 
faith. Faith in the grace of God is always liable to be taken as 
a pretext for moral sloth and inertia. This, however, is not the 
fault of faith, but of its being misunderstood. Misunderstood 
faith can use the principle of inwardness as a disguise for a false 
conservatism, which preserves the present ordGr not because of 
its element of divine creation but merely for reasons of personal 
privilege. All these misunderstandings cannot undo the truth 
that genuine faith, Math its silent revolution, is an incomparably 
more radical transforming power than outward reformation and 
revolution. 

This primacy of the " silent revolution " which is implied in 
the genuinely Christian distinction of centre and periphery does 
not, of course, exclude drastic action with a view to changing 
outward conditions and social structure. But two things will 
always distinguish the Christian from a secular revolutionary. 
First, structural changes will never be given first place because of 
their ambiguity and ambivalence. Though the motive behind 
them may be truly Christian, they may work out in a very 
different direction. The best of laws may create the worst of 
results if handled by men of evil spirit. Second, the Christian 
will not be in favour of outward changes before the situation is 
" ripe " for them. Otherwise such changes may produce more 
confusion than good, and, if they are not prepared from within, 
they will not last or will last only by tyrannical enforcement. 
That is why those social changes, which are the result of Chris- 
tian motives, are more of an organic than of a violent nature. 
Radical as is the break between the old and the new in the centre, 
the change in the periphery — in outward conditions and 
structure — takes on rather the character of slow growth. Great 
Christians were never " revolutionary " in the ordinary sense of 



Ill] CHRISTIAN AND SECULAR REVOLUTION 41 

the word. The " revolutionary principle " in this sense is much 
more the product of equalitarian lationalism than of Christian 
faith. It is radically opposed to tradition whilst, in the Christian 
view of things, a high valuation of tradition is paradoxically 
united with an incessant push to renewal 

Modern man, who has emancipated himself from God's order 
and usurped the rights of God, has also made for himself the 
claim: "Behold, I make all things new". Having somehow 
become omnipotent in his dominion over nature, he thinks him- 
self able to throw overboard all tradition and to create a 
perfectly new order according to his own design. This new 
order, however? always carries the stamp of technical rationality. 
As he overlays nature with his man-made, artificial second 
nature, by technical civilisation, so he also substitutes for already 
slowly developed culture an artificial, planned civilisation, which 
is as ugly and inhuman and destructive of real creativity as those 
mushroom cities of the late 19th century. 

Christian faith alone is capable of combining tradition and 
renewal, because it is based upon the unity of God the Creator 
and God the Redeemer. Tradition alone leads to petrifaction ; 
renewal alone leads to dissolution, artificial planning and tyran- 
nical centralisation. The Christian faith affords the possibility 
and necessity of both : of reverent preservation and continuity 
and of radical change and indefinite growth. Both are equally 
necessary for a truly human civilisation. 

One last thing must be said. Whilst it is true that the Chris- 
tian faith lives by paradosis, by handing over the Gospel truth 
to every new generation, it is equally true that this handing over 
creates real living faith only where this tradition is capable of 
renewal itself. -The Gospel truth is the same throughout all 
centuries. But the human interpretation of this truth must be 
new in every new epoch, and the forms in which this tradition 
takes place must be different, according to the times and cir- 
cumstances. Mere traditionalism is the death of the Church, 
just as mere revivalism is its dissolution. So it is in the Church 
itself— in its functioning as the means of veritable tradition 
and renewal — that this duality of conservation and reformation 



42 TRADITION AND RENEWAL 

has to take place. As a matter of fact, it is not two things but 
one thing. The Church has to give the world the living Word 
of the living God. It is by His living Word that God preserves 
the world, and it is by His living Word that He renews the 
world. Where this Word is alive and preached as a living Word, 
and where it is received in real faith, it cannot but do both: 
preserve what God wants to have preserved and renew what God 
wants to have renewed. 

ft is this mysterious unity of tradition and renewal which is 
the only hope in a world in which false conservatism and false 
revolutionism have brought about a tension which spells disaster. 
To enter into that mysterious unity of traditioirrand renewal is 
the meaning of the old and much abused word, conversion. 
And it is there where the mere exposition of thought has to stop 
and the decision of the individual has to come in. 



IV 



EDUCATION 

THE cultural level of a country is often judged by the 
measure of education of its population. What is educa- 
tion? There is an aspect of education which is not 
specifically human. We know the adequate and at the same 
time touching Ssertions of animals in training their young ones 
in the arts of their life. Human education is a continuation of 
these exertions, by which the older generation introduces the 
younger generation into the habits and arts of their own life. 
Human education, then, is a form of tradition; its purpose is to 
pass on the experiences of the earlier generation, their convic- 
tions of what is necessary to life, their conception of values and 
standards, their habits and practices, and to train those who 
come after in all these. The subject of education is primarily 
the community : in the first place the family, but also the clan, 
and finally the political community. Education, like all tradi- 
tion, is in its essence an activity of the community. In primitive 
societies education ends with a rite of reception into the com- 
munity of the adult, by which act he now becomes responsible. 

It was an event of revolutionary importance when Socrates 
for the first time proclaimed as the true purpose of education 
individual independence, spiritual self-reliance. His maieutic 
method aimed, as the name indicates, at simply drawing out, or 
bringing to the light of the day, what is hidden in every man. 
He therefore questions the principle of education that had been 
dominant hitherto, namely, its character of tradition. The 
Socratic teacher does not pass on; he does not give, but wants to 
make the pupil independent of anything given and of any giver. 

The idea of education as evolution, development, was thus 
discovered. But this new individualistic idea was never accepted 
— either in the time of its first prophet, or later on — to such a 

43 



44 EDUCATION [LEGT. 

degree as to displace the older idea, with its basis in social tradi- 
tion. On the contrary, the Socratic method of education always 
remained an exception. The material weight of the things to be 
passed on and the necessity of social tradition was so great that 
the Socratic element of education was always confined within 
narrow limits. 

All the same, there was even in the traditional idea an element 
somehow akin to the Socratic method, namely, the element of 
training, the development of those capacities and skills which 
seemed useful to the community. Training is different from 
passing on. Its aim is individual mastery. After all, even the 
act of passing on, of tradition, contains at bottom an element 
which we might call Socratic; appropriation of what is to be 
received. Wherever tradition is alive and not mechanical, this 
element of individual, active appropriation must be present. On 
the other hand, the Socratic idea has its limits. The mind or 
spirit cannot be educated or formed without offering it certain 
materials for self-active appropriation. The Socratic ideal was 
based on the a priori elements of that which dwells in the mind, 
and is therefore independent of history. Socratic education 
evidently has a rationalistic, anti-historical leaning. 

It is obvious that Christianity introduced into the world an 
idea of education which — at first sight — is completely opposed 
to that of Socrates. In the Christian conception the historical 
is everything, the a priori nothing. Christianity is in itself para- 
dosis, traditio, of historical revelation. Something divinely given 
has to be passed on. Furthermore, Christianity is essentially 
social. The individual has to be fitted into the Christian com- 
munity and finally — and this seems to be the sharpest opposite 
to Socrates — the aim is not the self-active spirit or reason, but 
the acceptance of something given which is beyond reason. The 
victory of Christianity, then, seemed to carry with it — in its idea 
of education — the complete denial of the Socratic idea. 

This was so much the case that even in the moment where 
western education began to emancipate itself from Christian 
leadership — i.e. in the Renaissance— this fundamental opposition 
was not yet felt. The return to antiquity did not take place at 



IV] THE SOGRATIC ELEMENT 45 

first in the direction of individual independence or autonomy, 
but as an appropriation of the antique cultural values as distinct 
from the Christian ones. Education was, in fact, so entirely 
conceived as passing on, that at this time the question was 
merely: what is to be passed on? It seemed to be possible to 
take over the cultural heritage of antiquity without thinking 
independently for oneself. But the masters of antiquity could 
not but create a spirit of independence and the courage^ of 
thinking for oneself. It could not be long before the specific 
character of Socratic education was rediscovered, and the idea of 
education as the development of the indwelling germs of the 
individual mirftl was given first place. Descartes' Discours de la 
mithode, with its regress upon the a priori certainties, and 
Leibnitz's Monadology, with its principle of the monad without 
window, gave the Socratic idea a new philosophical and meta- 
physical weight. Lessing's treaty, Die Erziehung des Men- 
schengeschlechts, is important in two respects. First, Lessing 
is the first modern thinker who understood the whole history of 
humanity from the point of view of education, divine education, 
thus showing the way to Herder and German idealistic human- 
ism. Second, Lessing tried to combine Christian revelation 
with the Socratic idea of education. He interpreted divine 
revelation as being a means of accelerating the development of 
the a priori possibilities lying in man's spirit. It was, however, 
Rousseau who, for the first time and in the most comprehensive 
manner, applied the Socratic ideal to the education of children 
and youth, and thus even surpassed Socrates. With Herder the 
idea of education as Bildung, i.e. organic development of all 
inward possibilities lying within man's nature, is magnificently 
based upon a universal conception of history. All human 
history is but one great process of spiritual development. 

What German humanism since Herder understands by 
Bildung has no parallel in any other country or language. That 
is why the word cannot be translated. By a grandiose synthesis, 
Christianity was combined with the Socratic idea of education. 
What Goethe, Schiller, Humboldt, Fichte, Schleiermacher and 
Hegel understood by Bildung is a synthesis of historical tradi- 



46 EDUCATION [LECT. 

tion or communication and Socratic self-development. The 
product of this synthesis is the truly gebildete Persdnlichkeit. 
This gebildete Persdnlichkeit, the highest point man can reach, 
is an individual in whom all latent possibilities are fully 
developed by the appropriation of that which is given to him 
from outside, from nature and history. The whole wealth of 
historical heritage, of antiquity and Christianity, is here con- 
ceived of as a means of education. Education itself, however, 
is 'understood Somatically as self -development. History plays 
the r61e of the Socratic teacher. It is the stimulus that brings 
forth the development of inner wealth. Contrary to the rather 
polemic attitude of some of these thinkers with regard to Chris- 
tianity, the decisive influence of Christian personalism appears 
in the fact that the idea of personality dominates within this 
system of education. Goethe's confession hochstes Glilck der 
Erdenkinder ist dock die Persdnlichkeit is not only his, but that 
of the whole classical epoch of German idealistic humanism. 

Within this conception of Bildung, the idea of education has 
outgrown the limitations within which it was confined up to 
Lessing. Education understood as Bildung is not a process 
which is completed by reaching the age of maturity but one 
which only then comes to its own. Bildung is the real life of 
the man who is spiritually awake. It is the very essence of 
humanity to become a truly gebildete Persdnlichkeit; it is the 
highest aim towards which man can strive, according to the 
Orphic word: "Become what Thou art". Education gains 
here a new meaning of immeasurable width and depth. Man 
is a microcosm containing and reflecting the macrocosm. He 
can and shall appropriate to himself the totality of nature and 
history. At the same time nature and history are meant to 
become united in his personality. 

The idea of Bildung in German idealistic humanism is cer- 
tainly one of the grandest and most beautiful achievements of 
the human mind. Although it was the life programme of a 
small ilite, and although it was so ambitious that it could be 
shared only by men of high culture, it has exerted a great in- 
fluence. From this ideal, the renewal of the German university 



IV] THE IDEA OF Blldung 47 

(for which the newly created University of Berlin was the model) 
took its start. The schools of secondary education followed its 
example. The enthusiasm and the deep sense of responsibility, 
with which in this epoch the reform and extension of popular 
education were tackled, have their origin in the impulses which 
came from the spiritual heroes of Weimar, Jena and Berlin. 
The role which this spirit of education played in the national 
awakening of the German nation, leading to the War of Libera- 
tion against Napoleon, cannot be ignored. The influence which 
this powerful and high-minded philosophy exerted, far beyond 
the German frontiers, is well known. It had even a political 
effect in the democratic movement of 1848, which was unfortu- 
nately crushed by Bismarck. 

All the same it was not by chance that in the political, as well 
as later in the social competition of forces, this movement came 
to an early end. The ideal of Bildung was, as we have already 
mentioned, too exclusively fitted to a spiritual elite and could 
not be adapted to the requirements of the common man. This 
is the decisive limitation of idealistic humanism. It was an 
educational ideal for spiritual heroes; it could never become 
popular. The adaptation of this conception of education to 
primary schools and family education proved to be impossible. 
It is true that the school programmes, with a few phrases origin- 
ating from this realm, proclaimed beautiful things about the 
development of the total personality. As a matter of fact, in the 
real school education these phrases remain on paper, whilst 
actual education and training follow quite different, more 
practical, lines. 

Fortunately, there existed and still exists another much older 
idea of education, which is capable of being the basis of all, even 
the most popular, education : the Christian idea. This Christian 
idea of education, however, was never clearly conceived and 
worked out. In the Church of the first centuries, Christian 
education was limited to baptismal instruction, containing the 
elements of Christian doctrine and ethics, combined with family 
tradition. How this Christian family tradition and ethics grew 
up we do not know. We do know, however, that it must have 



48 EDUCATION [LECT. 

been very efficient in the first centuries, because otherwise the 
continuous growth of the Christian Church could not be under- 
stood. Christian personalities were trained who stood the test 
of life. The Christian idea of education was not worked out, 
because obviously this was not necessary. The passing on of 
Christian doctrine and morality, and the training for Church 
and family life, were sufficient. The first part, doctrinal 
instruction, was performed according to the didactic rules 
prevalent in the synagogue and in existing schools. The 
second part was performed, so to say, instinctively. 

The same is true, more or less, of the Middle Ages. For the 
simple Christians the catechism and Church distom seemed 
sufficient. For the more ambitious, there were the higher and 
highest schools of learning with their combination of Christian 
theology, philosophy and liberal arts. But for both, the simple 
people and the spiritual ilite, a large part in education was 
played by the Sacraments, which accompany the whole life from 
birth to death, and which at that time were observed daily. No 
doubt, the Church of the Middle Ages did a tremendous work 
of education by its religious apparatus and by its effective en- 
deavour to permeate the whole of life by its sacramental prac- 
tices. No wonder, then, that in this epoch the conflict between 
Christian theology and the Socratic idea of education did not 
become acute. The lack of a formulated Christian idea of educa- 
tion was covered by the actual educational work of the Church. 

This lack, however, became much more dangerous in the 
Churches of the Reformation. Here the sacramental training 
and Church habits were reduced to a minimum. On the other 
hand, preaching and teaching the doctrine of the Bible was 
pressed almost exclusively. These two facts together created an 
enormous educational vacuum. Whilst in theological know- 
ledge the New Testament origins of Christianity were redis- 
covered, it was almost completely forgotten that the original 
Christian Church was before all a living community, that the 
Holy Spirit worked primarily by means of communal life, and 
that at that time the younger generation received their Christian 
influence and instruction not merely through preaching and 



IV] ROME AND THE REFORMATION 49 

teaching but through training in Church life. The educational 
vacfuum, which became more and more obvious, is primarily due 
to the lack of capacity and even of endeavour on the part of the 
Reformation Churches to develop a Christian community life. 
Certainly, there exists a considerable difference between 
Lutheran and Calvinistic Churches. Calvinism, and even more 
the sects deriving from Calvinism, have paid much more atten- 
tion to the formation of living communities than the Lutheran 
and even the Zwinglian Churches, where the identification of 
Church and civic community worked in the opposite direction. 
But the tendency towards orthodox intellectualism developed 
the same vacuum even within the Calvinistic Churches. The 
orthodox intellectuals' emphasis on doctrine is the main cause 
of the educational vacuum of Protestantism. 

It is true that the intellectualist misunderstanding of faith — 
identifying faith with belief in doctrines — was a tragedy in 
the Christian Church, that had already begun in the second 
century. But up to the time of Protestant orthodoxy this fatal 
onesidedness was compensated to a certain extent by intensive 
ecclesiastical training and habit. Whilst the Reformation in its 
centre was the rediscovery of the non-intellectualist conception 
of faith, this new discovery was lost all too soon in the fight 
against the Roman heresy. The Reformation Churches became 
orthodox. The old intellectualist misconception of faith became 
dominant again, but was now much more dangerous than in the 
Catholicism of the Middle Ages, because all those compensatory 
elements, by which the Church of the Middle Ages had covered 
its bareness, were now lacking. Once Church doctrine, theology 
and catechism had acquired their almost monopolistic position, 
education was reduced to theological teaching. No doubt, even 
within Protestantism, Christian custom played its role and 
Christian training was an element of family life. But these 
elements were secondary and not sufficiently connected with a 
truly- evangelical community life. The resentment against 
Roman Catholic training resulted in discrediting training as 
such. 

We have to mention another factor of great importance — the 
fight of Reformation theology against the opinion that man 



50 EDUCATION [LECT. 

could co-operate with God in things of faith led to a conception 
of revelation which stood in opposition to the Socratic idea. 
Orthodox theological doctrine, as expressed for instance in some 
Lutheran Confessions, interpreted in mechanical terms the 
exclusive divine activity in the conversion of men. The active 
element of appropriation was eliminated. If you study the 
classical catechisms of the 16th and 17th centuries, which in 
many respects are masterpieces, you will see that the activity of 
the pupil is reduced to a minimum. The doctrine that the 
human mind to which faith is imparted is a truncus et lapis, has 
devastating effects upon teaching. The ordinary catechism 
instruction is an educational monstrosity. 

From this point of view, the Socratic revolution, beginning 
with Descartes and leading on to German idealism, was an 
historical necessity and an indubitable gain. Here the pupil is 
at last taken seriously as an active factor in learning. Against 
the background of orthodox passivism, one can understand the 
tremendous impression made by the educational ideas of the 
1 8th century, and also the energy and passion with which the 
orthodox system was attacked. Protestantism, in spite of its 
priceless Biblical insight, has led to an educational debacle 
which would have become much more apparent had not the 
revival of teaching in the 18th century and 19th century been 
carried on in the name of Protestantism. 

Up to the present day, the Christian idea of education has not 
been fully worked out. In that respect, Reformation theology, 
even in its best forms, has proved unsatisfactory, because it was 
never capable of combining the necessary Socratic element of 
active appropriation with the Christian conception of divine 
revelation. There are, however, two great exceptions to this 
negative general statement, two thinkers at least who have made 
most valuable contributions toward a Christian idea of educa- 
tion : the great Swiss educator, Pestalozzi, and the great Danish 
Christian thinker, Kierkegaard. 

In general, Pestalozzi has been misunderstood as being a 
follower of Rousseau and of German idealism, though, as a 
matter of fact, the basis of his pedagogical system is emphati- 



IV] MODERN SECULARISM 51 

cally Christian. It is true that Pestalozzi took over from 
Rousseau the idea of self-development, and worked out his 
pedagogical message according to the Socratic principle of 
development of the germs lying in man. In that respect he is 
at one with the main trend of the time. On closer inspection, 
however, we see an unbridgeable gulf between Pestalozzi's 
guiding principles and those of Rousseau and the German 
humanists. This appears already from the basic fact that the 
central idea in Pestalozzi's system is the Christian idea of lo^e. 
Education for him is education in love and for love. He is in 
complete disagreement with his contemporaries, and in complete 
agreement witk the Christian tradition, in putting the main 
emphasis on the education by the family, particularly by the 
mother, and in subordinating all education to the one belief that 
men become human by living in the love of God and in loving 
communion with their feUow men. Again he is thoroughly 
Christian in emphasising the dignity of manual work and the 
unity of man's body and spirit. Pestalozzi, in spite of his ideal- 
istic terminology, is a Christian prophet of humility, social 
responsibility, and life in prayer, deeply rooted in Biblical 
revelation and tradition. He has learned whatever was to be 
learned from his idealistic contemporaries and their idea of 
Bildung, but the basis of his instruction is neither Rousseau nor 
German idealism but Biblical faith. 

It is greatly to be regretted that the Christian Church and 
theology were prevented by intellectualism from understanding 
the unique importance of this first great Christian philosopher of 
education, and that they left it to the epigoni of German human- 
ism to develop and to propagate Pestalozzi's ideas in & direction 
foreign to the intentions of the master. A genuine Christian 
conception of education could have been gained from Pestalozzi, 
or at least developed, for he was the first thinker who had tried to 
combine the Socratic idea of self-development and spontaneous ap- 
propriation with the Christian faith in divine revelation. After 
what we have seen about the fatal misunderstanding of ortho- 
doxy in the matter of appropriation of divine truth, we certainly 
cannot seriously blame Pestalozzi for lacking in orthodoxy. 

...ii 



52 EDUCATION [LECT. 

It may seem rather astonishing that we should speak of Soren 
Kierkegaard in this connection, because this great thinker does 
not seem to have been very much interested in the problem of 
education. We are justified, however, in mentioning him here, 
because the dominant problem of his philosophy is the relation 
between the Socratic conception of learning and Christian faith 
and because his main interest was the truly active appropriation 
of the Christian message. Hence, we can understand his sen- 
tence : " The subject is the Truth This sentence, expressing 
better than anything else what he was after, is not an expression 
of romantic subjectivism, of Fichte's philosophy of the " Ego 
nor of Cartesian rationalism; it is spoken simply*out of his con- 
cern for genuine " existential " faith as distinguished from 
orthodox belief in a creed. Kierkegaard, however, has met with 
the same fate as Pestalozzi: the Church and the theologians 
failed to understand him. 

Kierkegaard's doctrine of the paradox, of the scandal, of the 
existential character of faith, has certainly exerted considerable 
influence on recent theology. But his doctrine of appropriation, 
which is at the root of all his dialectic, has not been understood, 
has not even been noticed. So far as Protestant theology is 
concerned, it did not fit in with the conceptions of sin and grace, 
as they were formulated by Reformation theology. The doctrine 
of sola gratia did not seem to leave room for Kierkegaard's con- 
cern for active appropriation. Protestant theology is still 
dominated by a mechanistic conception of God's activity in 
conversion. And this is precisely why Protestantism up to this 
hour has not been able to develop a Christian idea of education, 
and to relate Christian faith to the different spheres of 
autonomous cultural life. 

In their time, the Reformers had tried to solve this problem 
by making a distinction between Christian revelation on the one 
hand and secular science and arts on the other. By this simple 
distinction they were capable of combining with their theology 
a rather generous estimate and use of cultural values of the 
Graeco-Roman civilisation. In spite of Luther's fight with 
Erasmus and of Castellio's expulsion by Calvin, all the great 



IV] EXISTENTIALISM AND FAITH 53 

Reformers were also humanistic admirers of classical antiquity. 
This is particularly true of Zwingli and Calvin. Whilst their 
theology differed greatly from that of the humanists, they 
shared with them not merely their love of Greek and Latin, but 
also their high estimate of classical literature, poetry, philosophy, 
political science and science in general, so long as the question 
of free will did not interfere. But they left unsolved or even 
untouched the problem, to what extent Christians could and 
should learn from the pre-Christian pagan masters and left 
undefined the limit of what was or was not admissible. We 
certainly cannot blame them for not being capable at the same 
time of reforming Church and theology and of solving the 
problem of the relation between Christianity and secular 
culture. They had undoubtedly done enough ; their followers, 
however, did not have the necessary calibre to tackle the task 
which the great masters had left behind. On the one hand, 
they turned back to the medieval synthesis; on the other hand, 
they developed a narrow-minded Biblicism on the basis of verbal 
inspiration, which could not but lead to a severe conflict with 
science and to the cultural impoverishment of the Protestant 
world. The lack of a Christian conception of education was a 
serious handicap. 

This vacuum, however, became fatal directly Cartesian 
rationalism and German idealism produced the new and inspir- 
ing idea of Bildung 1 and when the 19th century, compelled by 
the development of natural science and modern industry, forced 
modern mankind to face entirely new problems. Whilst, in the 
time of the great German idealists, history and classical anti- 
quity were the primary material from which the education of 
the gebildete Persdnlichkeit was expected, the demands now 
became much more realistic and practical. Nature took the 
place of history ; the social and political problems and struggles 
of the present displaced the interest in antiquity. National 
consciousness superseded idealistic cosmopolitanism ; the claims 
of state and society left little room for the development of 
personality. A new idea of education, originating from a 

1 Culture. 



54 EDUCATION [LECT. 

naturalistic theory of evolution and from pragmatism, took the 
place of the two older traditions — the Christian and the idealistic. 
Education was now conceived as an adaptation to the social 
environment. 

The American philosopher, Dewey, was the first to formulate 
this new realistic idea of education on the basis of a naturalistic 
evolutionism. The extraordinary success which Dewey's 
educational programme had, even amongst those who did not 
agree with his naturalistic philosophy, is due in no small 
measure to the fact that he drew, more or less unconsciously, 
from humanistic and even Christian reserves. It is probable 
that even the great example of Pestalozzi had^its share in his 
educational conceptions. 

This is now our educational situation : a chaotic mixture of 
the most varied traditions and ideas : medieval and Protestant 
Christianity, Rousseau, German idealism, pragmatic natural- 
ism, Marxist economic materialism, nationalism and political 
totalitarianism. The question is whether Christianity is capable 
of producing a conception of education which can combine with 
the highest claims of Christian personalism the Socratic element 
of self-development on the one hand, the new insights of natural 
science and the practical requirements of economic and political 
life on the other. 

If we answer this question with a confident " yes we do not 
mean by this that this idea has already taken shape in our mind, 
but only that our understanding of the Christian faith makes it 
possible. We agree with the 18th century humanists that the 
idea of personality must be in the centre of education. But it 
is just in the understanding of personality that the roads part. 
From the point of view of Christian faith, personality is not 
something given, which only needs development, but it is a 
relation. Personality is rooted in the relation to God. It is that 
"self " of man which is called into existence by the divine 
" Thou '\ Its centre is responsibility, understood as the response 
of man to God's call. Its true realisation, and therefore true 
humanity, is existence in divine love becoming concrete in love 
towards our neighbour. This is Pestalozzi's idea of education. 



IV] THE CHRISTIAN IDEA 55 

We must, however, distinguish more clearly than he did between 
the divine calling to this existence and an innate possibility. 
This possibility does not He in man. It cannot be developed; 
it must be given. But Pestalozzi is right, against his orthodox 
critics, in maintaining that this personality does not come 
to existence without man's highest activity; it is not thrown into 
man, but man is called to it, so that nobody can take away his 
own responsibility. Out of this conception of personality a new 
educational programme can and must be developed, combining 
the Socratic element of self-development with the Christian 
concept of divine grace. 

All the powers and possibilities of mind and body, which are 
in man and which can and must be developed, are placed in a 
new relationship and unity by this central act, by which true 
personality is created. They are not denied but transformed. 
Nobody becomes a genius by faith. Mathematical or physical 
knowledge is not upset by the fact of conversion. There exists 
a certain autonomy of the powers of reason, imagination and 
feeling, given by the Creator, which have to be respected so 
long as they are not absolutised. These powers then have to 
be developed according to their own law, and this is the place of 
the Socratic element. But it is no more than an acknowledgment 
that all these powers are gifts of the Creator and subordinate to 
the highest personal and communal destiny of man, as it is given 
by the Christian faith, which can prevent them from anarchic 
competition with each other and unify them harmoniously. 
Furthermore, the development of innate powers has to take 
account of the fact that man is a sinner and that nothing in him 
is exempt from the destructive effects of sin. In this respect, 
however, a fundamental law has to be considered. The more 
peripheral or extraneous a sphere of life, i.e. the further it is 
removed from the personal centre, the less does the question of 
sin come in. It would be hard — though not impossible — to 
discover the difference between a pagan or atheist and a Christian 
mathematics, but we can certainly distinguish most clearly 
between a Christian and a non-Christian conception of freedom, 
of moral obligation, of marriage and family, because in all these 



56 EDUCATION 

questions the sinful " Ego " of man plays its role. The reformers 
were undoubtedly right when they were inclined to learn from 
Aristotle's logic but were rather sceptical concerning his 
ethics; they were right in enjoying classical poetry and at the 
same time criticising its pagan superstition or its moral con- 
fusions. Furthermore, a Christian idea of education will be 
distinguished by a positive appreciation of everyday life and 
economic work. It will not, in idealistic snobbery, ignore the 
fact that man has a stomach and must eat, and that he is created 
with sexual desires. It will not forget, in these spheres parti- 
cularly, that man is both God's creation and a sinner. It will 
not therefore discard the wealth of new knowledge which 
modern biology has given us, but it will refuse to accept pseudo- 
scientific mythology without fearing the reproach of backward- 
ness. It will not refuse to see man as a member of the animal 
realm, but will at the same time emphasise that his humanity is 
something perfectly new which cannot be derived from animal 
life. It will, however, interpret this humanity of man not so 
much in terms of his rational and creative capacities as in terms 
of personality, and will therefore subordinate both his natural 
and cultural requirements to his ultimate personal destiny. It 
will put love and personal responsibility in the first place and 
thus oppose the intellectualism and irresponsible individualism 
and aestheticism of modern higher education, which is so largely 
responsible for the cultural catastrophe of our age. In an age 
of collectivist totalitarianism, Christian education is particularly 
called upon to oppose the claims coming from that side and to 
emphasise the supreme value of personality and personal 
responsibility. 

These are merely a few hints indicating that there is a 
Christian idea of education although we may not yet clearly 
know what it is. Those who feel the calling to work it out will 
have to justify their claim to do so by making use of the most 
important beginnings — the contributions of Pestalozzi and 
Kierkegaard — and by seeing clearly the real crux of the pro- 
blem : the relation between traditio — Christian and otherwise — 
and Socratic self-development. 



V 



WORK 

MEN do not work as a matter of course ; still less do they 
want to work when they are not forced by necessity. Is 
working something essentially human, or is it alien to 
the human as such, and merely imposed upon men by outward 
necessity? There are societies belonging to primitive civilisa- 
tion — notably the Australian aborigines — in which men do not 
work. They merely catch fish and gather berries when they are 
hungry. There is, on the other hand, a state of highly 
developed civilisation in which the bearers of cultural tradition 
think it unworthy to work. The intensity of work in modern 
western civilisation is a historical anomaly. Perhaps the 
weakening of the will-to-work which we experience in some parts 
of Europe is a reaction against this anomalous tempo of work. 
At any rate it is a symptom of the unsolved problem of the 
meaning of work. 

If you ask, " Why does man work? " the answer is generally : 
"Because unless he works he goes hungry. If this necessity 
ceases, he stops working and plays." This answer is obviously 
only part of the truth. There are people who want to work, who 
do not feel at their ease without working, or for whom work is 
an obligation of self-respect. They would feel themselves to be 
idlers, parasites of human society if they did not take part in 
work, which is the basis of existence for civilised humanity. 
There are people to whom work is a religious obligation, a divine 
calling. The problem of the meaning of work leads us right 
into the ultimate question of the meaning of life itself. 

Few people philosophise about their jobs. One does work, 
and anyone who doesn't want to will soon see that he has 
to. For most people the question does not arise, because 
there is no alternative; that is why history often leaves us 

57 



58 WORK [LECT. 

without a definite answer. Most men work because they must; 
whether this is their only motive or whether, apart from 
necessity, there are other stimuli, remains an open question. But 
the question takes on specific urgency when under certain social 
conditions the necessity to work has been somehow loosened or 
even removed. It is because of this close connection with 
outward necessity that work is suspected of being a mere servi- 
tude of human existence, a burden which must be thrown off by 
those who have a higher idea of life. 

This was the view of classical antiquity. To work for the 
necessities of life is something degrading for men. Work is 
good for what the Greek called banausoi — the Helots and slaves 
—not for the free Hellenes. The Greek free man should be 
exempt from this necessity : he, the bearer of spirit, shall lead a 
spiritual existence. Certainly, he should not be inactive; 
activity belongs to the essence of the mind and therefore to a 
truly human existence. But this activity should not be work, 
it should not have anything to do with preservation of physical 
life. The free man ought to create, but he ought not to work. 
This accords with the Greek philosophical anthropology, 
namely, that the distinctive element of the human is the spirit, 
while the body is the partie honteuse of man's existence. There- 
fore free spiritual activity, grounded in itself and not tied to any 
biological necessity, is the only worthy existence for man. 
Useful work aimed at preserving life is a mere continuation of 
animal existence; biological necessity is the lowest category of 
human purpose, making the mind an instrument of animal 
instincts. 

This depreciation of useful work has never been expressed 
more clearly or rationally than by Aristotle. But in this, as in 
so many other respects, Aristotle is a true spokesman of typical 
Hellenic views. Along with the Aristotelian theory of values, 
this conception of work was introduced into the Christian 
Middle Ages and blended with the feudal class structure of 
society. Only it was no longer spiritual activity in the cultural, 
but in the religious sense, which forms the apex of this structure. 
The lowest class is that of the peasant, his activity being the 



V] CLASSICAL AND MARXIST CONCEPTIONS 59 

continuation of animal life; the highest is that of the homo 
religiosus; between the two extremes there is a scale determined 
by the Aristotelian classical opposition of spirit and matter. 

This order of values broadly determines the views of the 
cultured European. He distinguishes between " low " work and 
"higher" (cultural) activities of man. Economic activity, 
manual work, is " low whilst free, creative, cultural activity is 
" high And it is so much the higher as it is independent of 
the shameful link with the necessities of life. The highest 
spiritual activity therefore is that of the free artist or scholar 
who has not — or should not have — to worry about his living. 

This Aristotelian scale of values, which for centuries has 
dominated European civilisation, has not remained .unchal- 
lenged. It was in the middle of last century that a radical 
reaction took place in Karl Marx's economic theory of history. 
The devaluation of useful economic work gave way to its 
opposite, which we might call " the myth of the working man 
Economic work to produce the necessaries of life now becomes 
the real substance of human history and of man's life; according 
to Marx this is the theme of all history. And the dramatic 
factor is merely the distribution of the fruit of this work. Let 
us not forget that the Greek devaluation of economic work was 
possible only on the basis of slavery. Whilst the Athenian 
gentlemen were philosophising in the market place, their slaves 
had to do the drudgery under inhuman conditions, as beasts of 
burden, so that the Athenian gentlemen, having gained an 
appetite from their philosophical disputes, might have some- 
thing worth while to eat on coming home. Similarly the 
aristocratic-clerical class-system of the Middle Ages was possible 
only on the basis of agricultural serfdom, the thrall having to 
do the mean, low work for the higher and the highest ranks, 
the nobility and the clerical aristocracy. It is in view of these 
facts that the Marxian picture and its protest against hypo- 
critical ideology and fictions gain their power of conviction. All 
this cultural existence, it was said, was based upon exploitation. 
At the cost of the drudgery of the peasant, the higher classes 
could lead their parasitic, spiritual luxury-existence. Idealism, 



60 WORK [LECT. 

according to Marx, solves the problem of the meaning of work 
by dividing it into two parts — spiritual activity and economic 
work; acknowledging only the first as human, but at the same 
time living upon those who by necessity do the second. This 
idealistic conception, then, is characterised by an insincere 
dualism. It asserts the possibility of a spiritual life without 
economic interests, whereas the spiritual life can only be lived 
because the economic necessities are provided by others who are 
stupid or powerless enough to do it. 

I do not hesitate to give a large measure of credit to this 
Marxian " debunking " of a false, dualistic conception of work. 
By this Marxian reaction the worker — now the labourer — 
becomes the "real man". The one who, according to the 
Aristotelian and the medieval theories was the lowest, the pro- 
ducer of economic values, now becomes the true bearer of human 
history and civilisation. The working man is the hero of the 
social revolution and its eschatology. He is the centre of the 
new myth and the content of the new religion. 

This radical turn, however, would not have been possible 
without a thorough preparation in the bourgeois mentality and 
society. In a way, Marxism is only a last phase of bourgeois 
capitalism. It was then that the transvaluation of values from 
the spiritual to the material economic scale of values took place. 
That economic values are the highest, the genuine reality, is not 
an invention of Karl Marx, but of capitalist society of the 19th 
century. This pan-economism was practically the philosophy 
of the time, long before Karl Marx gave it the theoretical form 
of " historical materialism ". " Money rules the world." The 
dispute between Marx and the capitalists is merely concerned 
with the question who shall have money. The view they hold 
in common is that economic goods are the substance of life. 
Therefore they agree that the question why we should work 
cannot arise. Life consists of these two things : making money 
by producing material goods and consuming them. 

This revolutionary transvaluation of the Aristotelian scale of 
values, by which the lowest becomes the highest, means the 
self-sufficiency of the economic motive of work: one works, of 



v] "vocation" 6i 

course, in order to live, and life means enjoying the goods pro- 
duced. While the classical solution is based on a fictitious 
idealism — fictitious because it presupposes the very unidealistic 
separation of society into a cultural elite and a majority of 
uncultural, unfree economic producers — 19th century economics, 
both capitalist and Marxist, represents a practical materialism in 
which man's life and economy are ultimately identical. The 
first solution corresponds to an anthropology in which man is 
essentially spirit, imprisoned in a body. The second, materialist, 
solution corresponds to an anthropology in which man is essen- 
tially a body, and mind or spirit merely a concomitant 
by-product of the body, producing in its turn the so-called 
ideologies. Both solutions are equally unsatisfactory and 
unrealistic. 

Christian anthropology avoids the idealistic as well as the 
materialistic onesidedness. It takes man to be a unity of body 
and mind, because the body is created by God as well as the 
spirit. The classical hierarchy of values, calling the bodily life 
" low is impossible here. Therefore bodily work is in no way 
degrading, unworthy of men. Instead of the opposition between 
the " low " and the " high we find here the relation of ends 
and means, of " within " and " without The body is the 
organ and the means of expression of man's divine destiny. 
Man must not be ashamed of his body and its needs, both being 
created by God and therefore good. Work done by the body 
and for the body is not inferior, but a consequence of God's 
will. The Bible does not show any trace of an ascetic devalu- 
ation of bodily and economic life. The medieval predilection 
for virginity and for a religious life detached from the world 
has its roots not so much in Christianity as in Hellenistic 
antiquity. 

Luther's rediscovery of the Biblical meaning of " vocation " 
or "calling" had revolutionary consequences. In the Middle 
Ages it was only the monk and the priest who had a divine 
vocation, not the layman. The idea of the homo religiosus 
being, by his divine vocation, the apex of the social scale domi- 
nated the whole of the structure of feudal society, culminating 



62 WORK [LECT. 

in the Pope and — at the other extreme — the peasant in an almost 
slave-like abasement. He, of course, had no divine vocation; 
this was the exclusive privilege of the homines religiosi. It was 
a direct consequence of Luther's rediscovery of the New Test- 
ment message that every Christian, whether a priest, a monk, a 
king or a housemaid, being called into the service of God, may 
look at the work he or she is doing as a divine calling or vocation. 
There is nothing " low " about the work of a housemaid. It is 
just as " high 99 as reading the mass or the breviary. It does not 
matter what you do, provided that whatever you do is done as a 
divine service to the glory of God. 

By this new idea of calling or vocation the fatal dilemma is 
removed: the choice is between the highest valuation of the 
spiritual with a consequent devaluation of the economic physical 
work, or the removal of this dualism on the basis of a merely 
materialistic economy. If all work is divine service, it is 
ennobled by this highest calling. The differente in value no 
longer lies in the kind of work which is done, but simply in its 
having, or not having, this divine purpose. The housemaid, 
the peasant, the cobbler, the industrial worker have equal title 
to divine nobility as the judge, the abbot, the artist or the king, 
if they do their work as a divine " calling " or vocation. The 
valuation of work is shifted from the " what " to the " why " 
and "how". 

This new conception of vocation therefore ennobles the 
common man and his working day. Wherever a labourer does 
his work as God's servant, he has a better claim to a spiritual 
existence than an artist or scientist who knows nothing of 
divine calling. The traditional conception of spiritual work 
proves to be false. Spiritual work is done wherever work has 
this highest perspective. Our traditional conception of spiritual 
work originates from that abstract idealism which separates 
spirit and body. This spiritual snobbery is the counterpart of 
materialist vulgarism. Both are overcome by a truly Christian 
understanding of vocation. This high valuation of economic 
work as being a service of God cannot fall a prey to materialistic 
vulgarisation any more; the valuation of intellectual or aesthetic 



V] THE DILEMMA SOLVED 63 

work as being a service of God, no more and no less than the 
work of the farm-labourer seen in the same perspective, leaves 
no room for spiritual snobbery. The farmer, Johannes, in 
Gotthelf s Uli, der Knecht, who sits at night with his servant, 
Uli, to watch a calving cow, and uses this time to talk to him 
about his problems as a Christian brother, is enjoying a spiritual 
existence just as much as Johann Sebastian Bach composing a 
cantata in honour of God. 

Work conceived as the service of God is at the same time 
serving men. On this basis the division of labour cannot lead 
to the formation of classes or castes. Employer and employee, 
government and people, are brothers. If people take their 
Christian faith seriously, everyone knows that his specific 
function in society is service for the common good. Higher 
power, as involved in higher office, means so much greater 
responsibility for service. The Christian conception of vocation 
does not remove functional hierarchy. There is an Above and 
a Below, there is graded competence. But all this is functional, 
dienstlich, as we say in German — a term which refers to service, 
and has nothing whatever to do with distinction of value, nor 
any connotation of unfreedom. The soldier has to obey the 
officer, but the officer is not " more " than the soldier. In spite 
of functional subordination, they are equal. 

Karl Marx saw clearly that the division of labour, as it has 
developed in history, is closely related to the development of 
different kinds of feudalism, of caste and class systems in which 
the so-called " higher " exploits the so-called " lower He saw, 
further, that all sorts of metaphysical and religious ideas have 
been used to justify these systems of exploitation. It is hardly 
his fault that he did not see the true social consequences of the 
Christian idea of vocation, because empirical Christianity did 
not manifest much of it. It is within the so-called Christian 
world that the feudal structure of the Middle Ages and the class 
structure of modern society originated. Just as in classical 
antiquity society shows a cleavage between an unfree majority 
doing the economic drudgery and a free non-working ilite form- 
ing the basis of a cultural life, so in the age of capitalism there was 



64 WORK [LEGT. 

a cleavage between those living on independent capital income 
and those living on dependent wages. Because capital income is 
independent, while wage-income is dependent, the capitalist can 
decide how the proceeds of the work are to be divided, which, of 
course, he does entirely for his own profit. To oversimplify 
grossly : he takes the gold for himself, gives silver to the manage- 
ment, and the copper to the worker. In this fashion a modern 
caste system is formed within a society with equal political 
rights. There is a small ilite having the means of a rich cultural 
existence, while the larger masses are doomed to cultural 
helotism. The non-working elite lives at the cost of the hard- 
working mass, on the backs of which it produces and consumes 
the higher cultural goods. 

Onesided as this analysis may be, there is so much obvious 
truth in it that the masses of the working people, having once 
become aware of these facts — at the same time being misled by 
the onesidedness and exaggerations of this theory of exploita- 
tion — cannot have a right attitude to their work. This is one 
of the main causes of the present crisis of labour. The second 
cause seems to be of a merely technical nature, but is closely 
related to the first: the progressive division of labour, with its 
ultimate development, the assembly-line method of production. 

Once the owner of capital is separated from the actual work, 
his only motive is profit. In order to increase profit, he has to 
accelerate the process of work to get as much out of his invested 
capital as possible. The human factor, the relation of the 
workers to their work, is of secondary, if any, importance. More 
and more the machine thinks for the worker, while the share of 
the individual worker in the meaningful whole of the work 
decreases. The relation of the worker to his work becomes more 
and more impersonal and the meaning of his work becomes 
invisible. He seems to be merely an unimportant part of the 
machinery, whilst the meaning of what he does passes from his 
horizon. Much of the satisfaction felt by the farmer, in his 
intimate relation to natural growth, and the artisan in creating 
a useful object, is denied the worker at the assembly-line. 

The third cause of the crisis may be more important than the 



v ] THE MODERN CRISIS 65 

two others: unemployment and insecurity. The deep-rooted 
fear of unemployment shows more clearly than anything else 
that man does not work merely in order to get his living. Un- 
employment is dreaded even where its economic effects are 
minimised by insurance. Why then is unemployment so greatly 
feared? First, because it throws a man out not merely of a 
job, but of meaningful work which gives his life the dignity of 
creativity and service. Second, because it gives the unemployed 
the feeling of being a parasite of society. He feels himself, 
although innocently, under sentence of the judgment, " If any 
will not work neither let him eat He feels he is living at the 
cost of other people. He is ashamed to eat what others produce. 
It is this fear of unemployment, inherent in our present economic 
system, which more than anything else makes him hate this 
system and his working share in it. It is this permanent 
insecurity of the wage-earner which makes him conscious of his 
dependence an<^ his social rootlessness. 

It cannot be denied that these are features of our prevalent 
western economic system. It is another question whether a 
collectivist state-socialist system would make much difference to 
the worker's attitude to his work. A nationalised economy 
will not stop the progressive division of labour, nor abolish the 
assembly-line. The nationalisation of capital will not remove 
the dependence of the individual worker. Whether a state- 
controlled economy will be able to avert unemployment is at 
least an open question. On the other hand, it cannot be doubted 
— because it is already proved — that collectivism creates new 
factors which are unfavourable to a positive valuation of work. 
In a complete state-economy, the worker would hardly be 
allowed to strike or to choose his own working place, while he 
would always have to fear the punishment of an omnipotent 
employer. 

It is one of the main effects of a truly Christian view of life 
that one does not accept the alternative of capitalism or collecti- 
vist state-economy. This " either-or " is a false abstraction, 
disproved by history. Pure capitalism, as seen by Marx, does 
not exist any longer, because of the powerful reaction of trade 



66 WORK. [LECT. 

unionism and state legislation. We are, however, far from 
having exhausted all the economic reserves of a conception of 
work which is neither individualistic nor collectivist, based 
neither on a false idealism nor on a false materialism, but upon a 
Christian understanding of man and work. 

The attitude to work is ultimately a religious question. 
Experience shows that even within the present economic system 
it is not impossible — though it is difficult — to do one's work as 
service for God and men. If we keep in mind what St. Paul 
could expect from the slave members of the Christian com- 
munity, we may come to the conclusion that the primary factor 
in the crisis of work is the disappearance of the Christian faith. 
While it is true that all kinds of slavery are a disgrace to a 
Christian society and have to be fought, it is also true, and even 
more true, that a real believer can do his work as a service for 
God and men whatever the system may be. Capitalism in the 
Marxian sense is just as little reconcilable with o Christianity as 
is totalitarianism. Both have to be fought equally as destructive 
of the dignity of work. But while it is a serious obligation of 
the Christian Church to overcome this fatal " eitheror it is the 
blessing of vital Christian faith to preserve the conception of 
divine calling even in the most unworthy conditions. 

By the Christian idea of vocation all work is personalised as 
well as communalised. It is seen as part of one social body, as 
a contribution within a working community. Everyone does 
his service in his place and within its limits, and therefore gets 
his appropriate remuneration. The more this communal spirit 
is alive, the less need is there of the stimulus of privileges for 
specific services. From this ideal picture of a Christian com- 
munity, we can deduce the nature of those factors which 
threaten and destroy the community of work. 

First among these is the oligarchic misuse of the functional 
hierarchy, i.e* the exploitation of the functional subordinates in 
the interests of a selfish plutocracy or a tyrannical bureaucracy. 
Whether it is the capitalist " boss " or the communist commissar 
that is exploiting his functional position for selfish ends makes 
little difference. By this selfish exploitation of a position of 



V] DIVISION OF LABOUR 07 

power they make it difficult, i£ not impossible, for the worker to 
look at his work as a service. The second danger is ochlocratic, 
i.e. the fanaticism of equality which has no use for any kind of 
subordination. Nothing is more ruinous to the community of 
work than this egalitarianism. It destroys co-operation even 
more radically than does oligarchic misuse. The mere idea of 
radical equality poisons the atmosphere of work. Where the 
feeling is prevalent that any kind of inequality is as such an 
injustice, there can never be a positive valuation of work until 
every thing is equalised. This perhaps is the most serious 
element in the crisis of labour at the present time. 

Someone may object that of course division of labour and 
functional differentiation of competence must exist, but that no 
kind of privilege should be derived from it. Every servant of 
the community ought to be treated with absolute equality. Our 
reply is, first, that wherever this view of equality prevails, even 
functional differentiation will always be looked at with resent- 
ment and jealousy. Radical egalitarianism cannot stand any 
subordination. Secondly, as human nature is, it is impossible 
to get functional differentiation without the stimulus of 
privilege. Only in a society of perfect saints would it be possible 
to get a maximum of service and the necessary minimum of 
functional differentiation, with its different degrees of responsi- 
bility, without some kind of social privilege as a stimulus. 
Society has to pay for higher service the price of social privileges. 

To ignore this fundamental social law means to ruin any kind 
of social order. Even Bolshevist society had to learn that. But 
this fundamental law is discredited wherever the principle of 
egalitarianism dominates people's minds. It is beautiful if 
individual Christians, of their own accord, renounce all privilege 
— examples are not too frequent! — but it is entirely false to 
make this a general principle of Christian ethics and to discredit 
privilege in any sense as unethical. Wherever this radical 
egalitarianism takes hold of people's minds, its levelling results 
do not stop short of the dissolution of the social order. Equality 
is a principle .of the highest importance within Christian ethics, 
but radical egalitarianism is the most dangerous poison within 

F 



68 WORK [LECT* 

any working community. No society and no positive valuation 
of work is possible where this egalitarianism prevails. In saying 
this we do not favour unjust inequality, but we wish to discredit 
the identification of justice with equality. 

Apart from egoistic motives, it is only the belief in God's 
creation which affords a real motive for work. By it man knows 
two things : that being a spiritual-bodily unity, he is destined to 
work; and that by being created as a person in community, he is 
created for community in work. Wherever this faith prevails, 
the motive of work is guaranteed even in the most unsatisfactory 
conditions. 

Where there is at present a weakening of the will-to-work it is 
an outgrowth of our artificial civilisation and, at bottom, a conse- 
quence of secularism. As we have seen in our lecture on technics, 
Western society has not proved capable of mastering the tech- 
nical development in such a way that technical progress could be 
made serviceable to the human person and to^the life of the 
community. Futhermore, technical " progress " in combination 
with other factors has led to economic conditions — of which we 
shall speak in a later lecture — which make it difficult to keep 
the Christian conception of work. A worker who feels himself 
exploited by the capitalist can hardly be expected to think of his 
work in terms of divine " calling *\ But let us not forget that 
these economic conditions, as well as that false autonomous 
development, are themselves the consequences of a deep spiritual 
disorientation. Neither the crazy technical development, with 
its complete disregard for man and its mania of production for 
the sake of production and profit, nor the " capitalist system 
with its disregard for human personality and community, could 
have originated in a truly Christian civilisation. In addition, 
thi weakening of the will-to-work is due in no small degree to a 
false, abstract doctrine of equality derived not from a Christian 
but from a rationalist idea of man and to a Socialist or Com- 
munist utopianism which makes believe that in a completely 
socialised economy all problems would be solved. 

It is also true that modern technics, with its extreme speciali- 
sation, has made it hard even for good Christians to look on 



V] THE PROBLEM OF THE MOTIVE 69 

factory work as a divine vocation. We should not, however, 
overemphasise this element of the present situation. Difficulties 
arising from technical specialisation are not comparable in 
gravity with the others. They can be overcome by creative 
efforts on the part of labour and management. Such efforts are 
already being made and extensive study is going on with pro- 
mising results. The Christian community has a specific task in 
just this field, namely, to work out a concrete doctrine of 
vocation through its lay members who know the jobs and their 
threat to working morale, and to demand and to create such 
technical and psychological conditions as are necessary to regain 
the lost sense of work as a divine calling. 

On the other hand, it is necessary to reshape the social 
structure of the worker's world in such a way as to take away his 
feeling of being a mere cog in an impersonal machinery, 
exploited by impersonal forces. It will be part of this pro- 
gramme to 4jspel the great illusion of our day that the 
nationalisation or socialisation of industry would do away with 
impersonalism and exploitation. But, while all this is true, we 
should not lose sight of the fact that the main problem is 
neither technical nor social, but spiritual. So long as the process 
of secularisation goes on as it has been doing now for two or 
three centuries, I see no hope whatever of regaining a right 
atmosphere of work. Whether or not we achieve a reasonable 
compromise between Capitalism and Socialism, the problem of 
the motive of work will continue to exist even if suppressed by 
compulsion. A true solution can only come through a return 
to that conception of work which the gospel alone can give — 
the conception that work, whatever it may be, is the service of 
God and of the community and therefore the expression of man's 
dignity. 

Empirical Christianity has failed to work out this conception 
of work in an age of technics. It may not be too late to do that 
still, but it will need no less than a great revival of Christianity 
in order to make this theory effective on a national and world- 
wide scale. 

To close with, let us have a look at the other possibility : the 



70 WORK [LEGT. 

hypertrophy of the will-to-work, i.e. work-fanaticism. This 
modern phenomenon is to be interpreted as a spiritual Mangel 
krankheit} There is a vacuum in the soul, an inner unrest from 
which one escapes by work. Work-fanaticism is proportional to 
the poverty of die soul. As nervous people cannot keep still, man 
with his unrestful soul cannot but work. The modern Western 
world is somehow possessed with this work-fanaticism as a result 
of inward impoverishment. Of course there is also another cause 
of this phenomenon which, however, is closely related to the 
first, namely, the incessant increase of material claims. But do 
not let us forget that many who are not inwardly seized by this 
fanaticism of work suffer all the same from its consequences. 
Those who do not want to get under the wheels have to adapt 
themselves to the modern tempo of work. It is fair to say that 
Western man, from sheer absorption in work, no longer knows 
what it means to live. You may find even on a tombstone the 
words : " His life was work It is here that t^te fourth com- 
mandment comes in: the Sabbath belongs to the order of 
creation. Man is created by God in such a way that he needs 
the Sabbath. Where the Sabbath-rest disappears, the human 
character of life also disappears. 

It is a strange paradox of the present day scene that we are 
suffering from a work-fanaticism and work-idolatry as well as 
from a lack of will-to-work. This paradox cannot be understood 
merely by surface-psychology and sociology. Both these pheno- 
mena come from the same root, the loss of the sense of the 
eternal meaning of life. When a man loses this divine perspec- 
tive, he throws himself into work and becomes a work-fanatic; 
or he sees no meaning in work and runs away from it, if he is 
not compelled by necessity or by the state. Just as the true 
motive of work comes from having a place in God's plan, so the 
desire of the soul for quiet and true recreation comes from the 
awareness of a higher destiny. God requires of us both that we 
do work even if outward necessity does not force us, and that we 
do rest and give our soul a chance of breathing. It may be that 
in a near future the problem of leisure will prove just as pressing 
1 Deficiency-disease. 



V] WORK AND LIFE 71 

as that of work ; indeed it is already becoming one of the major 
problems of our civilisation. Just as man's work can be emptied 
of meaning, so can his leisure. The mere escape from work 
into leisure, and into work from an empty life, is no solution. 
The real solution is such a conception of life as gives room and 
meaning to both instead of exchanging one emptiness for 
another. It has been proved within the Christian community 
that a life grounded in God's will finds the right rhythm of work 
and leisure, as expressed in the fourth commandment. 



VI 



ART 

HUMAN activity is not merely working, producing 
useful things which are necessary for the preservation 
of life. The human spirit transcends this sphere of vital 
necessity. Man decorates his home, he adorns his garment and 
his garden, he builds not only a solid, but a beautiful house, he 
carves, he draws, he paints without any useful purpose, merely 
from the inner drive for beauty and self-expression. He makes 
poetry, he sings, he invents stories, he acts plays. If we ask for 
a word embracing all that, it seems to be again, as in the case of 
science, the German language alone which dares to form this 
all-comprehensive concept of Kunst, whilst the English and 
French, following the Latin tradition, speak of the liberal arts in 
the plural, including in them also what the German calls 
Geisteswissenschaften. This daring, comprehending concep- 
tion, which combines the arts of the eye with those of the ear, 
has the great merit of leading our attention to something 
common in them all, the element of creativity, which is 
detached from all usefulness and intent merely upon creating 
beautiful work for the enjoyment of its beauty. 

Many attempts have been made to solve the riddle why 
men do all this. It cannot be our task to add one more to a 
hundred existing theories of art, but merely to see how, from 
the Christian faith, this most mysterious and at the same time 
most enjoyable phenomenon of culture is to be understood and 
what its relation is to the Christian faith. 

At first sight, art seems to be wholly independent of religion. 
Kunst comes from konnen; a Kunstler is a man who can do 
something that others cannot. Similarly we use the word 
artist, sometimes in a very general sense. We speak of the art 
of riding, of skating, of tailoring, and so on. But we are con- 

72 



AN OBJECTIVE INTENTION 73 

scious that by art in the proper sense we mean something higher. 
Mere virtuosity is not yet art, although the transition may be 
gradual. We speak of art in the proper sense where works of 
permanent value are created. Often art has been defined as the 
production of the beautiful, and therefore the secret of art has 
been identified with the secret of beauty. But the idea of 
beauty seems inadequate to indicate the mystery of art. What 
has Hamlet or King Lear, what has Goya's " Bull Fight what 
has Strauss' " Eulenspiegel " to do with beauty? Beauty is a 
fascinating mystery, but art is more mysterious than beauty. 

Why do men create works of art? We put aside all accidental 
motives, such as gaining one's living, love of fame and power. 
The work of art is so much the greater as these motives are less 
prominent. Art is surrender to something supra-personal. It 
originates from an inner urge. It is pledged to a spiritual 
" ought " which is almost as severe as the moral one; we speak 
of artistic conscience. We honour Rembrandt who, in his early 
days a spoilt and prosperous favourite of society, in his later 
years lost the favour of the public because he painted according 
to his artistic conscience without any compromise with the taste 
of the public, so that he died in poverty. 

We know that the Aristotelian theory, which gives first place 
to the imitation of nature, is inadequate, even for the explana- 
tion of painting, whilst in all other arts the model of nature 
hardly plays any role. In any case, whether it be in poetry, 
painting or music, the work of art is the expression of something 
inward, passing on that inwardness to the one who enjoys it. 
Art therefore, in all its branches, is expression capable of im- 
pressing. But in distinction from speech, it is without direct refer- 
ence to the " receiver It has an objective intention, making it, 
to a certain degree, independent and indifferent as to whether 
there is somebody who might enjoy it or not. In medieval glass 
paintings there are parts which can normally hardly be seen by 
anybody but which are just as carefully designed and painted as 
the visible parts. The artistic expression is so united with the 
inward feeling, that both cannot be detached from each other. 
The artistic form is externalised inwardness. The true artist 



74 ART [LECT. 

does not like to speak of an " idea " of his work, he is— emphati- 
cally—not a double of the philosopher. Form and inwardness 
are one. The artist creating his work creates a second reality 
distinguished from nature by its anthropomorphism. It is 
materialised soul and exalted nature. The work of art is the 
product of imagination. The German word for imagination, 
Einbildung, is an aesthetics in a nutshell The power of 
imagination is the capacity to externalise inwardness or to 
spiritualise matter. Once more we ask: Why do men do this? 
And why do others enjoy the results? A negative reason is 
obvious: They want to transcend existing reality because for 
some reason it does not satisfy. Artistic creation is somehow a 
correction and completion of reality. The dramas of Shake- 
speare show us people like ourselves. Why then this duplication 
of the human tragedy and comedy? The persons of Shake- 
speare's tragedies are no duplicates of those of every-day experi- 
ence, they are the products of a sifting enhancement which cuts 
away what is casual and enlarges the essential. Art is conden- 
sation, omitting the unimportant and magnifying the important; 
art intensifies and elates, it brings order to the chaotic, gives 
form to the casual and shape to the shapeless, it exalts and 
ennobles the material reality to which it gives form. 

What, for instance, is the meaning of the verse in poetry? * 
If man wants to say something important, he tries to make as 
great a distance as^yossible between that and mere talk. He 
wants to liberate his speech from every-day casualness, he gives it 
gebundene Form. The free submission under a law, the mount- 
ing of springing life in a self-chosen discipline, the firm shape 
of that which otherwise is shapeless, gives his speech lasting 
form, nobility. 

Art, then, is the attempt of man to raise himself out of the 
casualness, lowness, transitoriness of every-day life to a higher 
existence. This is the elevating effect of all art whatever its 
content may he. There is nothing elevating in the content of 
Othello, but in its form, which gives to human passion a purity, 
a necessity and an intensity by which it represents a higher 
form of existence. All art strives with more or less success after 



Vl] THE ELEVATION OF EXISTENCE 75 

perfection which cannot be found in reality. Art is an 
imaginary elevation of life in the direction of the perfect 

Imaginary indeed! Of course a Greek temple or a Gothic 
cathedral are not imaginary, but very real, built of massive 
blocks. But the beauty of this work is an imaginary elevation 
of life, a perfection which does not belong to ordinary existence 
but stands apart. Art does not change our life. The aesthetic 
solution of a problem by which a poet gets rid of it is no real 
solution, no real liberation. Art originates from and lives 
within imagination; it is an imaginary reality, similar to the 
dream. As long as we dream happily, happiness is real, but 
when we awake this happiness is gone. It cannot be integrated 
into our reality; it stands outside of that continuity which we 
call reality. Reality is the same to-day and to-morrow, but the 
dream of to-night will not be the dream of to-morrow. When 
the sound of Bach's Double Violin Concerto, which filled me 
with heavenly joy, has faded away, it still somehow remains 
with me for a while, like a beautiful dream when I awake. But 
then comes reality which is not heavenly joy, but sorrow and 
conflict, which the beauty of Bach's Concerto cannot alter. 

This is the limit of art. It is imaginary, playing perfection. 
It is the greatness and the delight of art to be perfection; it is 
its limitation to be merely imaginary perfection. It is the 
danger of art that it is so powerful although imaginary. Is 
there really a danger in art? Is art not that one thing in our 
life for which we can be thankful and which we can enjoy 
without reserve? This indeed is our first response : as Christians 
we say : art is one of the great gifts of God the Creator. Works 
of art are not produced as a matter of course. Talent or genius 
is the decisive element, and this is a gift of the Creator. It is 
not in vain that the word " talent " is taken from the Biblical 
parable which speaks of trusteeship. What then is its danger? 
It lies close to its very essence. Its essence is to be imaginary, 
its danger is that imaginary perfection may be confounded with 
real perfection. Art then becomes a substitute for religion. 
One looks for something in art, which it is not able to give ; real 
elevation, real perfection. This confusion is what we call 



76 ART [LECT. 

aestheticism. Art is not to be blamed for it, and it can be said 
that the great artists have rarely become victims of this tempta- 
tion. This confusion of imagination with reality happens more 
often to those who enjoy art than to the productive genius. 

Furthermore, it must be said that art does not really displace 
religion, but rather fills a vacuum in the soul which ought to be 
Med by faith. But we cannot evade the question whether there 
is not a fundamental opposition between art and faith, as 
expressed in the second commandment of the Decalogue. 
" Thou shalt not make unto Thee a graven image, nor the like- 
ness of anything that is in heaven above, or that is in the earth 
beneath, or that is in the water under the earth." Can the 
believer in face of this unambiguous prohibition enjoy art 
without reserve? One might reply that the divine prohibition 
is not referred to art as such but to idolatry, that is, to panthe- 
istic confusion of Creator and creation. The question, however, 
remains whether art as the work of imagination and as imag- 
inary perfection does not involve a fundamental conflict with 
faith in the invisible perfect One from whom alone comes real 
perfection. Is there not a secret opposition between the enjoy- 
ment of heavenly beauty in the imaginary world of art and the 
hope in the real heavenly redemption? Is not art, at its best, 
some kind of parallel to pantheistic mysticism, both being an 
anticipation of heavenly bliss here and now? 

It seems to me, we must not be extreme on either side. The 
true artist is no ecstatic who forgets about reality. Great art 
has always been rather tragic than happy, just as we can say 
that tragedy is the highest form of art. In tragedy and in all 
tragic art, man is conscious of his predicament and of his need 
for redemption. It is only the artist of the second rank who 
want§ to deceive men and himself with the belief that art itself 
can solve the contradictions of human reality. One great poet, 
defining the origin and essence of his art, says: und wo der 
Mensch in seiner Qual verstummt, gab mir ein Gott zu sagen, 
was ich hide. We need not therefore take too seriously that 
mystical or pantheistic danger, great as it may be, but we must 
take account of the opposite possibility that art can, by its 



Vl] THE PROBLEM OF " CHRISTIAN ART " 77 

capacity to intensify and to emphasise the essential, show to man 
with particular impressiveness his real situation as a creature 
needing redemption. 

We have to face the problem of Christian art. First of all, 
Christian art is not merely a possibility, but a historical reality. 
Since the decay of the Roman Empire during more than a 
thousand years, European art has been " Christian At first, 
this does not mean more than that the majority of the works of 
architecture in this era were Christian churches, from the Byzan- 
tine basilicas of Ravenna and Monreale to St. Peter's in Rome 
and the baroque churches of Germany and Austria. It means, 
furthermore, that the sculpture of these centuries is primarily 
Church decoration, that the subject-matter of painting, too, is 
drawn mostly from Biblical stories of Christian legends, that 
poetry and music, up to the time of Bach, are dedicated to the 
service of Church life. It is, then, an indubitable fact — although 
a fact which noeds interpretation — that during more than ten 
centuries art in all its aspects was an expression primarily 
Christian in essence and served the Christian Church. The 
question remains, however, in what sense we can speak of 
Christian art. 

We should beware from the outset of two extreme views : the 
one is a naive confusion of Christian art with art, the contents 
of which or the themes of which are Christian. When certain 
painters of the 16th century Renaissance treat Biblical themes 
or Christian legend, it is obvious that this connection between 
Art and Christianity is merely an outward and casual one. 
Sometimes, as in the case of the great Peter Breughel, one might 
even call this relation ironical. Even if we allow for the fact 
that the religious expression of an Italian is, in any case, more 
declamatory and dramatic than that of a North European, and 
even if we grant that Roman Catholic Christianity in itself is 
more externalised than Protestant, still we must confess that 
there is a kind of Renaissance art which, in spite of its Christian 
content, cannot really be called Christian. On the other hand, 
we cannot acknowledge the formalist theory that it is of no 
importance for art to have a Christian content or indeed any 



78 ART [LEGT. 

content at all. Here, then, we are up against the difficult 
problem of form and content in art. 

First, it cannot be denied that in art form and not content is 
primary. It is great art, when van Gogh paints a sunflower, 
when Daumier paints a boulevard scene. It is not great art 
when Kaulbach, in an enormous picture, interprets the Refor- 
mation. One might say, then, that content is nothing and form 
everything. Futhermore, what should " content " mean in pure 
music? But, on the other hand, could you seriously contend 
that it does not matter whether Michelangelo chooses as his 
object the Biblical story of Creation and the Fall or treats 
some scene of e very-day life? Do you think that Bach could 
express his deepest feelings, as in his B Minor Mass, just 
as well by using some banal worldly text? Or that it was by 
chance that Rembrandt in his later years turned more and more 
exclusively to Biblical stories? What, after all, is form and 
content when an inward world has to be visibly or audibly incar- 
nated? The relation between art and religion, between art and 
Christian faith, cannot be accidental, even though there exists 
supreme art without any noticeable relation to religion. There 
must be some deep connection between art and religion and, 
in particular, between art and Christian faith. What is it? 

Let us start with Greek tragedy. It may not be of decisive 
importance that the Greek theatre grew out of a religious cere- 
mony, just as the great manifestation of Greek architecture and 
sculpture originated from religious life. But tragedy as such — 
the phenomenon of the tragic — cannot be understood without 
man's relation to the moral order of the world. Without tragic 
guilt, no tragedy. It is not by chance that a Christian tragedy 
does not exist. Not because there was not enough dramatic 
talent to form a tragedy, but because Christian faith and the 
tragic understanding of life are irreconcilable. This form of 
art then, tragedy, has a definitely religious but certainly no 
Christian basis. How could you separate here form and con- 
tent? Take a parallel from within Christian times : the Biblical 
oratorio and the musical Mass, where the text supplies incom- 
parable musical possibilities. Certainly, there do exist oratoria 



Vl] CATHOLIC AND PROTESTANT 79 

of an entirely secular character; the musical form of an oratorio 
is not necessarily tied to the Christian content. But it cannot 
be a matter of chance that so many of the greatest works of 
music are those in which Christian texts are interpreted by- 
music. 

Even if we understand musical art merely from the point of 
view of dynamic expression, we would still have to take account 
of the fact that there are emotions of the soul, tensions and con- 
trasts, and therefore a dynamism which cannot be found apart 
from religious, nay, even Christian faith. If you think of the 
" Sanctus " or the " Kyrie eleison " of Bach's Mass, you can 
hardly deny that such music could not be created but by a 
deeply Christian composer. Take another example: It is 
hardly to be denied that the Roman Catholic faith has a closer 
relation to the arts of the eye than the Protestant, that, on the 
other hand, Protestant church music has reached heights which 
no Catholic composition has attained to. Roman Catholic 
faith tends to the visual, its relation to the visible is essentially 
positive, whilst Evangelical faith clings to the Word and has 
only an indirect and uncertain relation to the visible. That is 
why painting disappears in the Protestant Church, whilst 
church music acquires an importance which it never had before. 

The relation between art and religion, art and Biblical faith, 
must not be studied merely to answer the question as to what im- 
portance the religious element has for art; but also from the 
other viewpoint, to answer the question whether religion and 
Christian faith do not in themselves tend towards artistic 
expression. The Christian community through the ages has been 
a singing community. Christian worship is hardly thinkable 
without a hymn, psalm, chorale or anthem. The praise of God, 
joyful thanks, and passionate supplication of the congregation 
almost necessarily take shape in singing. There is hardly a more 
alarming, though infallible criterion of the decline of Christian 
community life than the decadence of Christian church music 
in the last two centuries. The Christian hymns that have been 
invented and sung during the last century have little to do with 
art, whilst the choral melodies which abounded in the first two 



t$0 ART [LECT. 

centuries of the Reformation churches were works of art of the 
first order; even Bach, who did not himself produce one, showed 
almost envious admiration of them. 

Not every live Christian is ipso facto also a church musician, 
but where musical talent comes within the life-stream of faith 
and within the magnetic field of a true Christian community, 
church music is born inevitably. The same can be said with 
regard to the relation of faith and poetic form. All the great 
prophets of Israel, from Amos to the anonymous writer of the 
exile, were also great poets. The weakening of poetic power 
goes hand in hand with the weakening of prophetic originality 
in the later Old Testament prophets. There is hardly a word of 
Jesus which is not a little poem and some of His parables are 
poetry of the highest order. We can hardly imagine Luther's 
prophetic genius apart from the powerful rhythm of his hymn, 
" A mighty fortress is our God That is Luther ! Who is 
able to delimit here prophetic faith and pontic expression? 
Both are so united in this hymn that the power of faith and the 
power of expression cannot be distinguished. 

A similar relation is to be observed conversely: in respect 
of impression. The religious hymn is not merely a necessary 
expression of faith, but also an effective means of faith. It is as 
if sacred music " tuned the soul " for faith. As the Marseil- 
laise was a powerful factor in spreading the spirit of the French 
Revolution, in a similar way really Christian music can kindle 
faith. The music of Bach and Schutz has this effect, but not 
that of Wagner. There are works of Bach to which, though 
they are pure music without any text, one could add the 
adequate Biblical words. We know by now that his most 
abstract composition, Die Kunst der Fuge, is Christian theology 
expressed in the form of immensely complicated fugues. 

Something similar is a common experience in the sphere of 
architecture. A Gothic cathedral generates a certain kind of 
reverent feeling, without there being any direct indications of 
the cultus. The very structure of the Gothic church, being an 
expression of medieval religion and theology, impresses the 
mind with that same spirit from which it originates. It is utterly 



Vl] ^ RELIGION AND ART 8l 

inept to build atl modern bank in Gothic style. If the so- 
called Gothic civil architecture of the Middle Ages does not 
have this character of dissonance, it is because in that era all life 
was permeated by the spirit of its theology and piety. How far, 
however, this Gothic structure is Christian, and how far 
neoplatonic mysticism is its root, is another question. 

If then there exists an indubitable relation between faith 
and art on the side of expression as well as on that of impression, 
we cannot avoid the question what the fate of art will be in a 
thoroughly secularised society where faith has ceased to be a 
formative factor. Indeed, this question is not merely academic 
in our time. It would not be historically correct to claim, on the 
basis of what has been said before, that the decline of religion 
must necessarily carry with it the decay of art. History gives 
many clear examples to the contrary. Greek art reached its 
zenith at a time when religion had already begun to decay. 
The same is true of Renaissance art in the 16th century, and 
French painting was at its best in the age where positivist and 
even materialist philosophy dominated. Again, a similar 
observation can be made about German music from the time of 
Mozart onwards, the only exception, confirming the rule, being 
Bruckner. And if instead of speaking of epochs we think in 
terms of individual artists, it would be hard to discover any 
definite proportion between artistic power and perfection on the 
one hand, and religious intensity on the other. Alongside 
Michelangelo and Fra Angelico, we have Raphael, Leonardo 
and Titian ; alongside Rembrandt, we have Peter Breughel and 
Vermeer; alongside Bach, we have Gluck and Strauss, not 
to speak of certain schools of first-rate art with a decidedly 
frivolous concepdon of life as background. 

Let us remember once more that Kunst comes from konnen, 
that artistic genius is a natural disposition, and as such indiffer- 
ent to religion or any philosophy of Hfe. Whether a man who 
is born with creative genius is deeply religious or indifferent to 
religion, does not in itself increase or diminish his creative 
capacity. But in spite of this we venture to contend that in a 
society where religious faith is dead, or has been dead for a 



while, art also decays. It is difficult to prove ihis assertion from 
history, because, whilst there have been times of religious 
decline, there never has been an epoch of predominant atheism. 
There may be one exception to this rule : our own age, as far as 
certain countries are concerned. But this period has not yet 
lasted long enough for us to draw definite conclusions. All the 
same our assertion does not hang in the air, for there are strong 
reasons for its validity. 

Whilst it cannot be said that faith or religious power is a 
necessary presupposition of art, two statements can hardly be 
denied. First, that creative genius combined with religious depth 
produces ultimate artistic possibilities which otherwise do not 
exist. Secondly, no artistic life can thrive on dehumanised soil. 
Where men are no longer capable of deep and great feelings, 
where the spiritual horizon has lost infinity, where the under- 
standing of life is devoid of all metaphysical or religious depth, 
art cannot but degenerate to mere virtuosity, and creative 
originality exhausts itself in inventions whicfi may be witty, 
striking or pleasant, but which cannot move the depth of the 
heart. The grand passions, which are the source of all genuine 
art, are not a phenomenon of merely psychological dynamic. 
Grand passions are not merely a matter of temperament or 
instinct. Their greatness originates not from natural disposi- 
tions but from spiritual tensions which do not exist any more 
where thinking clings to the surface of things. 

We touched on this point when we spoke about tragedy. 
Christian faith in itself cannot accept the tragic view; but being 
in itself the victory over tragedy, it presupposes the understand- 
ing of the tragic. Where there is neither understanding of the 
tragic nor Christian faith, where all relation to something trans- 
cendent and absolute has disappeared, where crude naturalism 
and materialism have taken the place of religion and meta- 
physics, great passions, deep feelings and those mysterious 
longings of the soul out of which great art is born, disappear 
also. The decay of the truly human necessarily brings with it 
the decay of beauty and mystery. This decay of the truly 
human, however, cannot be avoided in a materialistic world. 



VlJ RESPONSE TO SECULARISM &$ 

When man is cnjt off from the third dimension of depth, when 
he lives on the surface of mere utility, animal instinct and 
economic rationality, the element of humanity vanishes. This 
assertion, I think, has been sufficiently proved in the first series 
of these lectures. 

We now are in a position to see the dual fact: art in its 
dependence on, and its independence of, religion. The depend- 
ence is absolute only in an indirect sense, relative and partial in 
the direct sense. In so far as the depth of human existence is 
founded ultimately in the " third dimension ", in religion and 
metaphysics, and in so far as the Christian faith produces the 
deepest and most human kind of existence, art is dependent on 
it. In so far, however, as in the individual case and for a certain 
time this deep humanity can exist after the faith which has 
produced it, has disappeared, like an evening light after sunset, 
like the marvellous Abendrot in our Swiss Alps, art can persist 
for a certain wjiile in individuals or during a whole generation 
after the sunset of faith. But this Abendrot cannot be of long 
duration. The stock of human values created in a time of faith 
is soon exhausted in a time of faithlessness and with it the possi- 
bility of real art. The humanity of man is much more historical 
than we usually think, and that is true of art. 

I think we are justified in applying this general observation to 
our time, although we have to do it with great caution. If what 
I have just said is correct, we should expect that the secularisa- 
tion of modern mankind — which, although fortunately not 
complete, is the characteristic feature of the modern age — must 
have its effects on art. And we should guess that this effect 
must be a certain loss of depth and at the same time a tendency 
in two directions : barbarism or crudeness as a result of the lost 
distinction between man and animal nature on the one hand, 
and a certain abstractness as a result of formalism, because of 
the disappearance of metaphysical and religious content. Now, 
with all the reserve which my little knowledge of contemporary 
art puts upon me, I think that these tendencies are indeed quite 
obvious in the artistic production of our time, although the 
reaction against them is also to be felt, and in a quite remarkable 

G 



84 ART , [LEGT. 

degree. But this reaction against barbarism ?!nd formalism is 
at the same time also a reaction against secularisation and to 
this extent proves our thesis. 

Let me point out another feature of modern art which is a 
necessary result of what I called the loss of the third dimension 
of depth. Where men lose their religious faith, art is apt to 
take the place of religion. That danger, which as we have just 
seen is immanent in all art, becomes real. Art itself becomes 
the highest value, aestheticism becomes the religion of the time. 
It can hardly be denied that this is true for a good many of our 
contemporaries. The imaginary perfection and elevation of 
life which art gives them becomes a substitute for real salvation. 
They live in their imaginary world of artistic creation as in a 
sort of earthly heaven or paradise, measuring all life by their 
art and artistic genius. If I am not wrong, this is one of the 
elements which account for the sad condition of the French 
nation. The prevalent aestheticism of French cultural life has 
broken or at least seriously damaged its moral backbone. The 
religion of art is a poor substitute for true religion as a basis of 
civilisation. 

Still, real faith has not vanished. On the contrary, it is just 
in the sphere of modern art that we find, along with barbarism 
and formalism, most impressive signs of a spiritual awakening 
parallel to the reawakening of Christian theology and religious 
philosophy. Perhaps we may venture to say that the art of our 
time confirms what we have seen happening in other fields, that 
the low point of the secularist movement is already passed. At 
any rate, the battle is on and all of us are engaged in it. 

To close— let me take up once more the question raised in 
the beginning. Why do men create works of art? What is 
the function of art in the human household? For the creative 
artist himself this question hardly exists. To him art is a 
" calling To some of the greatest artists it is a divine calling. 
They follow an inward "must" which permits no further 
derivation except the religious one. For most men, however, 
who are not artists, but mere lovers of art, the answer is, from the 
Christian point of view ; art is the noblest form of resting from 



i 

Vl] THE FUNCTION OF ART 85 

the struggle of litfe, closely related with the quiet of the Sabbath 
in the Biblical sense. All work, even the highest spiritual work, 
produces a kind of hardness and cramp. The man who knows 
nothing but work becomes soulless. Art is the noblest means 
of re-creation. It cannot redeem our soul, but it can " tune the 
heart", even for the highest: for communion with God. It 
never produces or creates faith, but it can support the Word of 
the Gospel, which creates faith. It can open the closed soul and 
help it to relax in the most human way from the stress of every- 
day life. That is why we sing in our church services and why 
we should not underestimate the function of real church music. 
But apart from this highest function, man needs relaxation, 
especially if he is engaged in intellectual work. Art is the bene- 
ficent mediator between spirit and sensuality. It is a spirituali- 
sation of the sensual and the sensualisation of the spiritual. It 
is a necessity primarily for those who do not live in immediate 
contact with nature. Art is therefore, before all, a necessity for 
the city man. What Luther and Bach have said of music is 
true of all art: it is the servant of God to help his sorrowful 
creatures, to give them joy worthy of their destiny. 



VII 



WEALTH 

A LL civilisation is built upon material goods. So long as 
l\ man lives " from hand to mouth so long as there are 
M JLno permanent material goods and fixed property, civilisa- 
tion cannot arise. Notwithstanding the moral and social 
dangers of wealth and the acquisitive instinct, the fact remains 
that higher civilisation presupposes a certain material wealth 
and stable conditions of property. One cannot deny that 
cultural life always has a certain bourgeois character. The 
beginning of civilisation coincides with the transition from 
nomadic life to agriculture and permanent residence. It is not 
by mere chance that the word culture originates from agricul- 
ture. Agriculture is the primary stage of man's mastery of 
nature. Agriculture brings with it permanent and communal 
residence and city-building, which in its turn involves the 
crafts and division of labour. Division of labour again makes 
possible barter and its rationalised form, money. 

Of course, historically, the first property of man is neither 
soil nor house nor money, but the tamed animal and the 
weapon. The nomad is proprietor of his herds; this property 
is, so to say, entirely natural. The struggle between mine and 
thine, the problem of property, becomes acute only through the 
competition for soil and particularly because of individual 
agricultural property. On the other hand, the development of 
individual personality seems to be closely related to individual 
property. Where the peasant works a field that does not belong 
to him, where he is not economically independent, he will 
hardly become morally free. It is a law deeply rooted in man's 
nature that man ought to be free to dispose of the produce of 
his work, that its fruit " belongs " to him. Wherever this law 
has been disregarded, as in the absentee-proprietorship of the 

86 



I 

PERSONALITY AND PROPERTY 87 

Roman Empire!^ this has been a cause of cultural decline. 
Individual property is an important ethical value. We should 
not forget, however, that what nowadays is called individual 
property is of a very different nature. Modern individualism 
has transformed the firm relation between man and " his " soil 
into its very opposite, making agricultural soil an object of 
capitalist speculation. 

A similar relation to that which exists between man and soil 
obtains also between man and his house and his tools. In order 
to develop as a free personality, man must have certain things 
that belong to him. It is true that even a slave — like Epictetus 
— may consider himself a free man, as did the slaves of the New 
Testament Church, considering themselves as free in Christ. 
But as a general rule, the connection between individual pro- 
perty and the development of free personality can hardly be 
denied. A certain economic independence is a prerequisite of 
free personality. Private, i.e. individual, property is recognised 
in the Bible as a matter of course, although it is never considered 
as an absolute right. It is limited by the idea of stewardship 
under God and by the regard for the common good. The short 
experiment of Christian communism in the community of 
Jerusalem does not really form an exception, because everyone 
was free to place at the disposal of the community whatever he 
thought fit. 

As has already been said, division of work, together with 
permanent residence, makes possible barter and money. Money 
is the abstract form of material goods. This abstraction, like 
all abstraction, includes both great potentialities and great 
dangers. With money you can buy everything : land, houses, 
industrial products, and even labour. The economics of money 
compared with barter may be compared to the relation between 
algebra and simple arithmetic. Where money has become the 
main material good, quantity tends to prevail over quality. The 
desire for wealth becomes infinite, I cannot imagine an infinite 
number of concrete material goods, but I can easily add an 
indefinite number of ciphers to any given figure. That is why 
money becomes a great danger to social life. In itself it is a 



88 WEALTH [LECT. 

most valuable invention, freeing the exehang^ of goods from 
chance and other limitations and giving economic life a new 
mobility. 

Material property, necessary in itself, becomes deeply pro- 
blematic through the sinful nature of man, in two respects: 
first, with regard to the relation of material goods to other 
values ; second, with regard to the relations between men. Let 
us call the first danger practical materialism. In itself man's 
desire to acquire property is necessary both for the individual 
and for society. Cultural life can develop only where a certain 
surplus of means beyond bare existence is granted. A nation 
can apply itself to cultural production only where its energies 
are not entirely occupied by the production of the necessities of 
life. On the other hand, interest in material property tends to 
become isolated and monopolistic. Instead of being a means of 
life, wealth becomes the main aim. The necessary acquisitive 
instinct degenerates into mammonism, money, the abstract 
form of goods, playing a large part in this dangerous develop- 
ment. The lust for property becomes particularly dangerous 
when it is combined with the lust for power. Money becomes 
the primary means of domination over others. And this is the 
second form of the sinful development of material property. 
Man wants to be wealthy at the cost of others, and he wants 
to be wealthy in order to replace social responsibility by 
domination. 

These two negative aspects of material goods are as old as 
civilisation. Their most primitive forms are theft and robbery; 
their more refined, but not less pernicious, forms are unscrupu- 
lous competition and exploitation, the use of power for material 
advantage, and the use of money to wield power. The motive 
of power has two aspects : people may desire material goods in 
order to get power, or may use power in order to get material 
goods. All these possibilities are realised even in the most 
primitive civilisations. They have taken different shapes in the 
various epochs with their different social, economic and political 
structures, but basically they are always the same. It is of no 
small importance to see this semper idem, because otherwise one 



VIl] % MONEY AND CREDIT 89 

is easily deluded^by slogans putting the blame on specific social 
structures. Whether the economic structure is primarily agri- 
cultural or industrial, whether it is characterised by barter, 
money or credit, whether the political structure is monarchic, 
aristocratic or democratic, we see always the terrific interplay of 
man's lust for wealth, ruining his own soul and endangering the 
life of his fellow men and general culture. On the other hand, 
the identity of the basic forms should not make us overlook 
differences arising from the various social, economic or political 
structures. 

We have already seen that money, the abstract material good, 
accentuates certain evil developments, if not necessarily, at least 
as a matter of fact. In a similar way we now have to think of 
certain other factors tending in the same direction. Just as 
money is an abstract form of barter, credit is an abstract form 
of money. It is an abstraction of a higher order. In both 
cases abstractym is in itself a positive factor; it widens out 
the narrow limits of economic life, set by the more concrete 
forms of goods. By credit one is enabled to work with the 
money of others, paying them a certain interest as a reward for- 
lending their money, or giving them shares proportional to 
one's own gains. This expansion and intensification of economic 
possibilities at first sight looks quite harmless and useful. But 
upon closer inspection it carries with it great dangers. It creates 
income without work on the one hand, and it separates economic 
production from economic power. The non-working money- 
giver controls the actual work and the distribution of its profit. 

This new economic technique of the modern age, however, 
reached its full importance only in combination with the 
transition from craft to machine industry. The tool of the 
craftsman is cheap and can be owned by anyone. The machine, 
however, the factory, the industrial plant, is expensive; the 
individual cannot afford it, he is dependent on credit. Indus- 
trialisation is possible only in combination with credit, in its 
two forms: interest-earning and share-taking credit. Herein 
originates that system which we call capitalistic, and which at 
first is a merely technical device that must be sharply distin- 



90 WEALTH ' [LECT. 

guished from what we call the '* capitalistic sp.rit Taken for 
granted that all the persons concerned are good Christians, free 
from greed or egoism, this capitalistic system combined with 
industrialism would work for good. But just as money, the 
abstract form of goods, brings with it danger, even more does 
capitalistic credit become morally dangerous as soon as our 
moral hypothesis ceases to hold. In its combination with 
egoistic motives, this credit system becomes what is called 
capitalism in the evil sense of the word. Why is that so? 

First, in expanding the possibilities of profit-making, it also 
intensifies the profit motive. This is the effect of the doubled 
abstraction. Just as money can be more easily desired in 
indefinite quantities than concrete goods, profit-bearing securities 
can be more easily desired indefinitely than money. The pure 
quantification of the material goods tends to unlimited desire. 
Second, the development of the capitalist system means the 
gradual separation of ownership of the fiools — machine, 
factories, etc. — and actual working with those tools. It creates 
dependent labour and independent capital. It is particularly 
the absentee-owner, the anonymous shareholder who, not know- 
ing those who actually do the work and their conditions, is free 
from those moral inhibitions of the profit motive which are 
likely to function wherever work is done in personal coopera- 
tion. Third, the difference in economic power between the 
dependent workmen and the independent proprietor of the 
productive capital goes on increasing. Fourth, this economic 
power, concentrated in a few hands, may become so great that 
it can influence and perhaps even control political power. Big 
business is an important factor in world politics. 

So far, we have followed the analysis of capitalism given by 
Karl Marx, which, generally speaking, is correct. But certain 
corrections in his picture are necessary. Like his teachers of the 
Manchester school of economics, Karl Marx also presupposes 
the pure homo oeconomicus, taking for granted that the person 
who has economic power will use it without any consideration 
for the community or the human individual. This is wrong. 
The sense of justice and human personality is an important 



vii] m^vrx's "economic plan 55 91 

element even in a^capitpdist society. Second, Karl Marx has not 
taken account of the fact that through the trade-union move- 
ment and state legislation the evil consequences of the capitalist 
system can be and have been checked to a large extent. Capital- 
ism in Marx's sense, i.e. unlimited exploitation of labour in the 
exclusive interest of capital profit, hardly exists any more in 
Western society. All the same, the moral dangers inherent in 
the capitalist system have become and still are sinister realities : 
tremendous intensification of the profit motive, increased 
inequality with regard to property and power, social dis- 
integration. There does exist what Karl Marx calls a "pro- 
letariat ", i.e. enormous masses of men living under conditions 
unworthy of and detrimental to human personality, as well as 
to true community and spiritual cultural life. 

The necessary reaction against this threat from above has 
created what Karl Marx calls the class struggle, which, of course, 
is not merely a Communist programme, but a double-sided fact, 
poisoning and disintegrating society. The injustices inherent 
in and produced by the capitalist system and the proletarian 
disintegration of society have created a mentality within the 
world of labour which makes men inclined to listen to the 
slogans of totalitarian Communism, which in itself is the end 
of free society and of human culture. 

By all these factors the problem of material goods is accentu- 
ated in a way unknown to previous ages, unknown particularly 
to the time of Old and New Testament revelation. In the 
teaching of the prophets, of Jesus, and of the apostles material 
goods and property are regarded as natural consequences of 
man's being a creature. The Bible is not ascetic, either in this 
or in any other respect. In the Old Testament wealth is not 
morally discredited : it is a divine gift and a manifestation of 
God's blessing. But there already we do find a very critical 
estimate both of acquisition of goods and of property. The 
prophets in particular passionately denounced the egoistic 
profit-motive, which makes men forget God and trample upon 
their neighbours. They are uncompromising in passing»judg- 
ment upon the mighty and wealthy who use their power to 



92 WEALTH f [LECT. 

exploit and enslave the powerless. In tfee New Testament this 
critical attitude becomes even sharper, and wealth appears 
almost exclusively as a negative value. It seems almost impos- 
sible to be rich without forgetting the poor or without forgetting 
God. The man who enjoys his wealth without being moved and 
worried by the sight of poverty cannot be a disciple of Jesus. 
But even there we do not find a general moral disqualification of 
wealth or the postulate of poverty. The use which the medieval 
theology made of Jesus' word to the rich young man is a mis- 
understanding. There is nothing like a general precept or 
" counsel " of poverty in the teaching of Jesus. Wealth is not in 
itself evil, but its temptation is almost irresistible. While in the 
church of Corinth there are " not many wealthy still there 
are some, just as among those who followed Jesus there were 
some who had means, without being blamed for it. 

It is then very difficult, if not impossible, to gain direct norms 
from the Bible for present-day problems of economic life, in so 
far as they are predominandy structural. Attempts have been 
made to derive from the Bible a general prohibition of interest, 
and therefore a general opposition to the capitalist system. This 
interpretation, however, identifies two fundamentally different 
things : interest in the Old Testament sense, and interest as the 
basis of the credit system, which is entirely unknown in the 
Bible. To take interest from money lent to a neighbour who 
is in need is a different thing from deriving interest from money 
or credit given to someone who wants to make more money by 
it. The prohibition of interest by the medieval Church has 
nothing whatever to do with Biblical teaching. 

On the other hand, it is obvious that in the age of technical 
industry and the credit system the problem of material property 
and acquisition is fundamentally different from what it was in 
the time when the farmer, the craftsman and the travelling 
merchant were the predominant figures of economic life. 
Material property in the modern sense includes power over the 
dependent non-proprietor and even power over the state 
machinery. While power in itself is not morally evil, it becomes 
evil almost inevitably through the possibility of misusing it. 



VIl] CAPITALISM AND THE CHURCH 93 

And this possibility a^ain becomes a fact almost inevitably if 
we take men as they are. The concentration of power inherent 
in the credit system is an enormous moral danger, both with 
regard to the just distribution of goods and with regard to the 
just distribution of economic responsibility and power. 

This danger, however, can be and is checked by two counter- 
forces which tend to create economic as well as political balance, 
viz., by organised labour and by the equalising interference of 
the state. Furthermore, it is checked by a third factor which is 
often under-rated and even ridiculed, i.e. by spontaneous self- 
limitation of those in whose hand is the main economic power. 
Whether it is from fear of Communism or of organised labour, 
or whether it comes from a real sense of justice and humani- 
tarian motives, the so-called capitalists have learned to restrict 
the use of their power. While, of course, this self -limitation is 
far from having reached the necessary level, it is certain, on the 
other hand, thaj without it things would be much worse. It is 
here that the Christian Church has its most immediate field of 
action, because within the Christian faith motive is more im- 
portant than structure. Economic power is not necessarily used 
unjustly, and therefore power is not in itself an evil, but a great 
temptation. Where power is controlled by just and disinterested 
motives, it does not lead to injustice and exploitation. A truly 
ethical control of motives, wherever it does take place, is a surer 
safeguard against injustice and selfish exploitation than any 
structural, i.e. legal and political, control. The change of the 
system is only a makeshift for the lacking ethical inhibitions in 
the use of economic power. Wherever the working man is not 
influenced by propagandist slogans, he does not resent the so- 
called capitalistic system, if he is sure that the " boss " is truly 
concerned about his welfare and led by the sense of justice and 
loyalty. However, this obvious truth is limited by two facts : 
first, that even the best-minded employer himself is part of a 
system which limits his good intentions; second, by the fact 
that with the development of big business the individual em- 
ployer more and more disappears. The law of big numbers 
makes itself felt and gives the moral problem of present-day 



94 WEALTH 

economy a particularly dark aspect. B<£caus$ the large majority 
of capitalists are motivated much more by the profit motive than 
by justice and goodwill, the capitalist system on the whole has 
morally bad effects, and would have them much more without 
the check of trade-unionism and state interference. 

That is the reason why so many seek the solution of the 
problem in a radical change of the system, in Communism or 
— what is merely another name for the same thing — State 
Socialism. They think that by such a structural change the 
injustices connected with the capitalist system would disappear. 
They postulate the nationalisation of all productive capital, 
convinced that by this measure exploitation of the powerless 
would be discarded and a just distribution of national income 
would be safeguarded. This medicine, however, would prove 
more dangerous than the sickness which it means to cure. 
By nationalisation the whole of economy is politicised. Every 
member of the working community becomes a functionary of the 
state. It is inevitable that this politicisation of economy would 
lead to the totalitarian state. Totalitarianism, however, means 
the end of personal freedom, a soulless mechanical monster, 
compared with which the evils of capitalism — great as they are 
— must be called tolerable. It is an illusion that in a socialised 
state economy exploitation disappears. The truth is that it is 
shifted from the economic to the political field. The political 
" commissar 99 takes the place of the economic " boss Political 
bureaucratic hierarchy takes the place of economic competition. 
It is a complete misunderstanding of human nature to think 
that greed and lust for power would disappear in a fully state- 
socialist society. The temptation to misuse power is nowhere 
so great as in a totalitarian system, because the state machinery 
cannot allow opposition or even criticism. In a completely 
nationalised economy the individual worker loses his freedom 
to choose his working- and living-place ; he becomes a state-slave. 

We do well to remember Montesquieu's great discovery, the 
system of " division of powers " embodying his idea : le pouvoir 
atrite le pouvoir. Apart from the moral motive — which, as a 
rule, proves to be weak in general— it is the only safeguard of 



VIl] POLITICS AND ECONOMICS 95 

justice. This principlejof Montesquieu presupposes a pluralist 
structure. Thus Jar & misuse of capitalist power has been 
checked by trade-unionism and democratic state interference. 
Both contain reserves which are not yet tapped. There are still 
great possibilities lying in the mechanisms of collective bargain- 
ing and of education for mutual understanding between labour 
and capital, in the further democratisation of economy, in a 
revision of the legal status of corporations, and in the moderate 
equalising function of the state. The alternative, "either 
capitalism or state socialism is a product of propaganda, of 
panic and of inadequate thinking. 

As we have already said, from the Christian faith no direct 
conclusions can be drawn for the solution of these complex 
and abstract problems. We have to beware of the short cut, the 
idea that a specific affinity exists between Christian community 
and communism. Christian communalism is at the opposite ex- 
treme from Stat^ Communism. It is the expression of spiritual 
freedom. Nowhere in the Bible do we find the idea that cor- 
porate or national property is better than individual property. 
What we do find is the idea of stewardship and of social respon- 
sibility. As we have already said, on the basis of Christianity 
there cannot be absolute property, but only property regarded 
as trusteeship under God. This trusteeship includes respon- 
sibility for one's neighbour. The question, however, which 
legal system is the best makeshift for those true ethical motives, 
is never touched, just as the Bible does not say which form of 
political government is the best to check the misuse of political 
power. 

Sometimes the abolition of the capitalistic system has been 
postulated from merely economic motives which are only in an 
indirect sense morally relevant. The idea was that only state- 
planned economies can avoid unemployment and economic 
crises. Certainly unemployment is a dreadful plague of modern 
society, but it is an obvious error to think that state economy as 
such would cure that disease. Economic crises could be avoided 
by compulsory economic world-planning, i.e. by a world state; 
but even then it is most doubtful whether it would have this 



96 WEALTH [LEGT. 

beneficial effect. On the contrary, it is WghJty probable that the 
clumsy functioning of state machinery would be a cause of per- 
manent economic crises. But even if we take it for granted that 
nationalisation of industry and complete state control of 
economics could liberate society from the evil of unemploy- 
ment, this gain would be bought at too great a price, the loss 
of economic freedom and, ultimately, of political freedom 
as well. 

Why is it that the idea of Communism or State Socialism has 
captured the imagination of the working-class to such an extent 
as is the case in our day? First, because the so-called free 
economy of the Western world has failed to a large extent to 
prove its capacity of providing for just distribution of national 
income and property, and of giving the working-man an 
adequate share in management. The Christian Church ought 
to take a large share of responsibility for this tragic failure, 
having omitted to instruct her lay-members atput their respon- 
sibility for social justice and having accepted as a matter of 
course the development of a kind of individualistic economy 
which, at bottom, was irreconcilable with the Christian con- 
ception of personality and community. The Church should 
not, however, try to prove her repentance by supporting the 
ideology and programme of State Socialism or Communism, 
which would necessarily produce a kind of society in which not 
only freedom, but justice also finds no place. Secondly, the 
Communist or State-Socialist idea appeals to a mentality which 
is almost exclusively fixed upon security and has lost the sense 
of personal freedom. This mentality is the product of seculari- 
sation, i.e. of the loss of spiritual values, particularly of the 
Christian faith in which both personal dignity and communal 
obligation are deeply rooted. 

Thirdly, the Communistic or State-Socialist idea is the logical 
consequence of an idea of man which identifies justice with 
equality and has no comprehension whatever of the element of 
subordination and differentiation which are inseparable from 
any live social order. This egalitarianism has created a deep 
resentment against anything which has even the faintest simi- 



vn] * the'" third way" 97 

larity with the famih) pattern of community. Of course 
Christianity has failed" in supporting a kind of patriarchism 
and paternalism which, in a technical world, could not but work 
out in autocracy and economic tyranny. But the Church is 
supremely right in affirming that the family pattern is the 
Christian pattern of all social life. What needs to be seen is 
that the family pattern must be interpreted and worked out in 
our day in quite new forms, doing justice to the legitimate claim 
of each member of the family to personal dignity and basic 
independence. * 

It is here that the Christian Church has a great task to fulfil. 
The Christian conception of man stands above the false alter- 
native of individualistic liberalism or capitalism and collecti- 
vistic State Socialism or Communism. Christianity is absolutely 
unique in presenting a conception of man in which true person- 
ality and true community are not only firmly connected with one 
another but, at J>ottom, identical. Wherever a community is 
firmly grounded in Christian thinking, neither individualistic 
capitalism nor collectivist Communism or State-Socialism are 
possible. The " third way " is inherent in the Christian concep- 
tion of man itself. That is why Christianity is called upon to 
lead the way wherever the third way is seen as necessary and 
wherever, out of economic life itself, new schemes of social order 
emerge which are neither individualist nor collectivist. 

At present collectivism is in the ascendent and individualism 
is on the wane. Christianity has the historical task of raising 
her voice against the great dangers for human personality as 
well as for community implied in the collectivist scheme. It 
can do so with even more conviction, since it is becoming 
evident on experimental grounds that this is not a case of 
striking the right mean between justice and freedom. In the 
collectivist society the individual worker will get less than he 
has at present in a society which has long ago ceased to be purely 
capitalistic, less both in material reward for his work and in 
political, social and cultural freedom. Collectivism means, 
before all, enslavement; but it also means poverty. What is 
encouraging for those who survey the present evolution in the 



g8 WEALTH [LEGT. 

social sphere is the fact that amongsfg those who used to be 
Marxian Socialists a deep change is taking* place, away from 
Marxism in its ideological as well as its economic and 
political programme. There is an obvious convergence of the 
thought and will of those who are trying to find a truly social 
liberalism and those who are out for a truly liberal Socialism. 
And it is certainly not by chance that where this reorientation 
takes place a new openness of mind towards Christianity 
becomes apparent. 

Up to now we have been speaking of the problems arising from 
differences of economic power. We have now to turn to the 
other great problem, that of excessive valuation of material 
goods as such. It is obvious that the capitalistic structure of 
economic life has intensified the acquisitive instinct and 
increased the striving for wealth. This practical materialism, 
however, is unlikely to be discarded in a nationalised economy. 
Against the auri sacra fames, State Socialist^ is no medicine. 
The valuation of material goods is independent of legal structure 
and depends on the whole conception of life. Greed, lust for 
property, is the most direct manifestation of worldliness. The 
man who does not believe in God and eternal life is likely to be 
more intent upon material goods than the man to whom the word 
" Seek ye first the kingdom of God " is a reality. Of course it 
might be objected that many Christians have been misers and 
profiteers. But let us beware of confusion; the man who is a 
miser and profiteer is ipso facto not a real Christian. This 
criterion is unmistakable in the New Testament. One might 
even say it is the first criterion. He to whom God's Kingdom 
is a reality cannot be a money hunter, and a money hunter 
cannot take seriously the Kingdom of God. You cannot love 
both God and Mammon. But where faith in God disappears, 
the vacuum which it leaves has to be filled with something. It 
need not be money. It may be a high spiritual good. But it 
may be money, and it is very probable that in most cases 
it is money which fills that vacuum. Spiritual goods are 
rarely capable of filling the heart when the basis of spirituality, 
God, has disappeared. Loss of faith usually means that 



VIl] CALVIlAsTIC CAPITALISM 99 

Mammon becomes Gc#. The practical materialism o£ the 
Occident is a diredt anci provable consequence of secularisation. 

We must say in this connection a few words about a famous 
theory pointing in the opposite direction : Max Weber's thesis 
about the connection between Calvinism and capitalism, which 
was accepted and spread widely by Troeltsch and also, though 
in a modified form, by Tawney. This theory seems to me a 
very dangerous half-truth. It cannot be doubted that the 
Calvinist-Puritan conception of the Christian life, according to 
which the elect has to prove his election by his life, combined 
with theXlalvinist emphasis on self -discipline and self-restraint, 
has contributed to the formation of capital; more exactly, to an 
increase of material goods which, not being consumed, were 
available for the expansion of production. It is obvious that 
these motives, combined with other factors, created conditions 
favourable to the development of the capitalistic system. But at 
the same time these motives were strictly opposed to what is 
popularly called the capitalistic spirit. The true Calvinists and 
Puritans were by no means money-grubbers, but energetic 
business men who regarded themselves as stewards of God, and 
therefore responsible to the community. It is not Calvinistic 
faith but, on the contrary, the decline of this faith and pro- 
gressive secularisation which led to the greediness which one 
has in mind when speaking in a critical sense about capitalism. 
The Quakers perhaps afford the best example. By thrift, sober 
living, hard work, and indubitable honesty they became most 
successful business men and acquired considerable wealth. They 
did not, however, succumb to the capitalist spirit, but proved by 
example that even within a capitalistic structure the relation 
between labour and capital can be just and humane wherever the 
power inherent in that system is not abused but used for good. 

The capitalistic system, however, did not develop because of 
men who worked much and saved the fruit of their work, but 
because world trade and industry demanded the creation of 
credit. There have always been hardworking and at the same 
time thrifty people, before Calvinism and outside it. The parti- 
cular development of the capitalist system in the so-called 

H 



100 WEALTH 

Calvinist countries has very little to d| with Calvinism, and is 
primarily due to the fact that these couhtriet' afforded the most 
favourable conditions for world trade and industry, and that 
they were populated by a type of people which in many other 
respects proved to be particularly energetic. This view of 
things is confirmed by the fact that the development of high 
capitalism took place in an age when the Christian faith, 
whether Calvinistic or not, was on the wane. It is the combina- 
tion of the credit system and industrialism, with that mammonist 
spirit which is the result of secularisation, that created the kind 
of capitalism of which the Western world should be ashamed. 
The tiny bit of truth lying in Weber's thesis is almost irrelevant 
compared with the enormous confusion which it has produced 
and the great injustice which it has done to Calvinist faith. 

The economic problems, i.e. the problems connected with the 
production and possession of material goods, have become so 
portentous in our time because the development of world trade, 
machine industry and the credit system took place in an age 
when the Western world was beginning to lose its religious basis, 
and when, therefore, money-making and the possession of money 
seemed more important than anything else. Furthermore, this 
development took place within a society in which an individual- 
istic conception of life worked towards the dissolution of 
community life. It can be easily understood that a society 
which was about to lose its religious and moral basis was hardly 
capable of solving the enormous social problems which the 
industrial revolution and the break-down of the patriarchal 
system had created. It can hardly be doubted that a truly 
Christian society could have overcome these difficulties at an 
earlier stage and would thus have prevented some of the worst 
features of the present Western civilisation. For it is the 
Christian faith that contains all the necessary forces of direction 
and healing which are adequate even to a very dynamic econ- 
omic life : a strong consciousness of personal responsibility and 
freedom, the willingness to serve one's fellow man, and the limit- 
ation of economic interest by the faith in a higher, eternal life. 



VIII 



SOCIAL CUSTOM 1 AND LAW 

IN primitive society, as well as in antiquity and in the Middle 
Ages, social custom (Sitte) and law can hardly be distin- 
guished. In their conjunction they are the solid order of 
life in which the individual is embedded; they are the skeleton, 
the permanent constitution, for the behaviour of the individuals 
and their mutual relations. Western society to-day is char- 
acterised by an enormous decay of social custom and, as a 
consequence, by an enormous increase of laws. The behaviour 
of the individual nowadays is only to a very small degree 
ordered by social custom, but to an increasing degree his free- 
dom is limited by legal prescriptions. The causal relation 
between the two facts is obvious : where social custom is strong, 
only a minimum of legal prescription is necessary. 

The destruction of social custom in modern times is closely 
connected with the development of individualism. The in- 
dividual wants to shape his life as it pleases him or as it seems 
good to him. He does not want to be controlled by the anony- 
mous power of social custom. He wants to have his liberty, 
and he also wants to decide according to his own conscience. 
The decay of social custom therefore is ambivalent ; it may be a 
sign of spiritual and moral independence, or it may be a sign of 
arbitrary subjectivism. In both cases it is the product of the 
emancipation of the individual from collectivity. On the other 
hand, it would be wrong to interpret the prevalence of social 
custom as spiritual inferiority and a defective sense of respon- 
sibility. Even a morally and spiritually mature man, who is 
perfectly willing to take full responsibility for his life, can 
acknowledge the necessity of social custom with regard to the 
common welfare. He would attribute to it the same function 

1 Sitte. 
101 



102 SOCIAL CUSTOM ANL> LAV/ [LECT. 

for society as to mechanical habit in individual life. It relieves 
life of unnecessary decisions and make! it free for decisions 
where they are really necessary. It would be stupid to deny 
the necessary function of individual habit. Without a great 
number of such habits, life is impossible. The same, the mature 
man might claim, is true of the function of social custom in 
society. He would add a second argument : to acknowledge the 
necessity of social custom is to acknowledge one's own limita- 
tions. Social custom may express the wisdom of the generations 
which is not consciously the wisdom of the individual. He 
would add a third argument : that not all people, if any, reach 
a state of complete moral maturity; and therefore people need 
the support of firm social custom. The necessity of social 
custom can be denied only by those who postulate that every 
individual be spiritually and morally awake at every moment, or 
who at least think that the absence of custom is more than com- 
pensated by the gain in individual responsibility. 

At first sight it might appear that New Testament Christian- 
ity, which puts the highest obligation of personal responsibility 
on the individual, and which believes in a continual guidance 
by the Holy Spirit, would leave little room, if any, for social 
custom. But this is not so. Good customs are acknowledged 
and recommended; sometimes good custom is appealed to in 
order to end discussion. On the other hand, the apostles warn 
people against bad customs and demand a complete break with 
them. Therefore the man who was converted to the Christian 
faith had to break completely with pagan custom in order to 
become a member of the Church. By this break a vacuum of 
social custom was created. But this vacuum was filled by some- 
thing else, by the order of life in the Christian community. This 
Christian order of life was a new kind of social custom. A body 
of rules, hardly conscious and never formulated, powerfully 
shaped the life of the individual Christian; its origin could 
hardly be traced and its necessity and rightfulness was never 
questioned. The importance of such Christian social custom 
in the early Church can harly be over-estimated. Certainly the 
great moral teachers of the early Church whose writings we 



VIIl] HABIT 103 

know not only enjoined, but also verified and corrected, these 
social habits of Ithe ^Christian community. The individual 
Christian, however, did do, or abstained from doing, many 
things differently from the rest of the world, for the sole reason 
that this was the social habit of the Church. 

Because social habit is formed unconsciously, and by its very 
essence is beyond people's criticism, there is great danger of 
every good custom degenerating into bad custom or into mere 
convention. Furthermore, social habit sometimes has no other 
purpose than effectively to separate one social class from another. 
The Court nobility, the upper classes, develop special customs 
and even complete codes of behaviour from the mere instinct of 
exclusiveness. The function of these customs is to distinguish 
those who belong to the upper circles, and so to prevent others 
from intruding. In a similar way habits are formed in other 
sections of society which for other reasons wish to be distin- 
guished and separated from the rest. Where this becomes 
conscious, such custom turns into a sort of private law. 

Social habit is a most complex thing: primeval religious 
customs long forgotten, political and military measures, obsolete 
legal institutions, prescriptions of long abandoned techniques, 
survive as social habits. "Everybody does it" — without knowing 
why, even if it is apparently senseless. AH the same, this con- 
servatism of social habit is not merely social inertia, but an 
instinct for the preservative power and necessity of social habit 
in general. It is an instinct for the necessity of a certain 
irrational factor, of a rule of conduct, the meaning of which 
cannot be thoroughly grasped. That is why the typically 
enlightened man, who acknowledges as truth only what he can 
himself understand, naturally despises and opposes social custom. 
It seems to him unworthy to subject himself to a rule which he 
does not thoroughly understand. The age of the Enlightenment 
therefore was the time when social custom was cleared away, 
just as, about the same period, the old fortifications and 
towers of former centuries were cleared away in European 
cities, because they were merely obstacles to modern traffic. 
Indeed, how much old rubbish has been swept away since the 



* r r 

104 SOCIAL CUSTOM AND L AlW [LEC1. 

Enlightenment I How much easier to purvey, and how much 
lighter, are our modern cities! How much Snore rational life 
has become! 

If this parallel between architectural style and way of life 
holds good, the comparison will not be entirely in favour of the 
modem age. It can hardly be denied that the picture of a 
modern city is characterised by a complete lack of character and 
style. Architectural style is the expression of a common mind 
and feeling. In the age of a great style, even the simple work- 
man builds well. The style builds for him. There is a more 
or less unconscious rule of building, directing the individual 
builder. The same is true of social habit : the age without style 
is also an age without custom. The individual is isolated, left 
to himself; there is no direction, no aim to be unconsciously 
followed. Everyone has to find his own style of life, and this is 
simply beyond him. The philosophy of the Enlightenment, 
being itself the heir of a great past, laid too heavy a burden upon 
the individual. The 17th and 18th centuries could indulge in 
an enthusiasm for freedom and emancipation without fearing 
chaos, because there were still the powerful integrating forces of 
the past, resisting chaotic dissolution. But in the 19th century 
the social structure begins to fall to pieces, and social chaos is 
waiting at the door which is opened in the 20th century; the 
reaction has already set in, in the shape of totalitarian com- 
pulsion. 

In this present age, Western mankind vacillates between 
complete social dissolution and complete compulsion. Social 
custom as a uniting and controlling power has been reduced 
almost to nothing, apart from small groups of society. The 
individual is left to his own conscience and to his own good 
pleasure. No way of conduct is marked out for him. He has 
to decide for himself. Modern man has now begun to become 
disinclined for this super-abundance of personal responsibility; 
at the same time he is afraid of chaotic dissolution. From 
extreme individualism he swings over to a collectivist totali- 
tarianism, finding it either in the Roman Catholic Church or in 
the Communist state. Protestantism, however, having identi- 



VIIl] THE PROTESTANT VACUUM IO5 

fied itself wrongly with individualism, is no longer regarded as 
a spiritual powe£ providing social cohesion and direction, 
because it was not capable of producing customs which would 
direct the individual without absolutely binding him. There 
is the same vacuum as in Protestant education, which we 
discussed in a previous lecture. 

The less social custom, the more compulsory law. This truth 
needs no proof in the age of totalitarianism. Man, having lost 
the sense of direction in a time of complete freedom, turns to 
the opposite extreme, to that society in which everything is a 
matter of compulsion. It must be acknowledged, however, that 
the tremendous increase of the legal apparatus and the pro- 
duction of laws has other causes as well. Modern economic life 
has become so intense and complex that increased compulsory 
regulation became inevitable. The fast-growing world-traffic 
has made necessary, so to say, a universal traffic-police to lay 
down compulsory rules of social life. 

This quantitative increase in state regulation, however, is not 
the only characteristic feature of recent times. Alongside it a 
qualitative change of greater importance is taking place, by 
which the totalitarian danger becomes imminent. In earlier 
times common law was a pre-state element, a fixed social 
relation. English common law is still independent of the state 
on the one hand, and hardly distinguishable from social custom 
on the other. For the Continental European of our time, 
English common law and the whole legal practice of England 
is very difficult to understand, because on the Continent common 
law has been displaced by codified law; the only remainder of 
common law there is what we call Gewohnheitsrecht (custom- 
law). But neither the term " common law " nor Gewohnheits- 
recht tells the whole truth. In the German word Recht there 
is a reminiscence of the relation between law and justice or 
righteousness, which is lacking in the word " law Common 
law in the English sense can exist only because and so long as 
there is a close relation between law and morality. On the other 
hand, the expression Gewohnheitsrecht is inadequate, because it 
is not a matter of mere custom, but of common moral conviction, 



106 SOCIAL CUSTOM AN1* LAW [LECT. 

In older times the legal sense or consciousness, what we call 
Rechtsbewusstsein, was closely related to ( justice. Law had not 
yet the formal technical character which it has now. That is 
why the jurists of previous centuries could think of positive law 
as being merely a special form of natural law, so that there could 
be no real clash between the two. While the relation between 
law and justice or morality was obvious and close, the relation 
between law and state was much less obvious or acknowledged. 
Certainly the authority of the state was even then necessary to 
enforce law. But the king was rather the protector than the 
creator of law. The power of the state stands behind the 
common law to safeguard it, but law itself is, in principle, inde- 
pendent of the state. The idea that only by the state does .a 
rule become law is entirely foreign to the people of older times, 
as it is still foreign to the English people. 

Whatever may be the cause or causes of this change, the fact 
is undeniable that on the Continent law is ur^erstood by the 
jurists as meaning law of the state, and that the jurists consider 
the state to be the only source of law. It is probably the fact of 
the codification of common law in the early 19th century which 
has contributed more than anything else to this unfortunate 
development. In the same degree as law has been exclusively 
linked up with the state, it has lost its connection with social 
custom and morality. Everything which the state proclaims 
as a rule is Recht, whatever its moral quality may be. And 
nothing which the state does not proclaim as a rule is Recht, 
however just it may be. The close connection between jus 
naturale and jus divinum on the one hand and positive law on 
the other is in that way completely denied and disrupted. 

This change has a double consequence. The first is a formal- 
istic conception and development of law. Everything which the 
state declares to be a rule* — all administrative machinery and 
procedure — is just as much law as those laws which order the 
conduct of the citizens and upon which rests the distinction 
between what is permitted and what is forbidden, what is lawful 
and what is unlawful. What in older times was Recht as distin- 
guished from Unrecht, " lawful " as distinguished from " unlaw- 



VIIl] THE |rATE AS SOVREIGN 107 

ful ", has now become a subordinate part of an immense body 
of administrative rul^s and prescriptions for business transac- 
tions. It is no more the content but the form which is decisive. 
All rules and regulations which the state places upon the statute 
book are considered as the one body of law; and thus the 
conception of law is formalised, and has almost completely lost 
its connection with justice and morality. 

The second change is of even greater importance. Whatever 
the state declares as law is Recht, even if it is the very opposite 
of justice and morality. The state is no longer the protector, it is 
now the producer of law. The state is no longer under the law, 
but above it. As there is no law but that which the state gives, 
there is also no law above the state, by which the state can be 
called to account. There are no primary rights preceding the 
laws of the state, no human rights which the state has to acknow- 
ledge and which it cannot repeal. The state has become 
sovereign in a jense which in the Middle Ages was sometimes 
applied to the monarch: princeps legibus solutus. The state, 
being the only source of law, cannot but be itself legibus solutus. 
The state can declare as law whatever it likes, which means that 
the formalism of the new conception of law includes or leads to 
state absolutism. This new conception of law then has a marked 
tendency to totalitarianism. The totalitarian state of our time 
is the practical consequence of this development of the modern 
conception of law. What is to be said from the Christian point 
of view about this whole development of the conception of law? 

Every reader of the Bible knows the close relation which 
exists between law and the divine will. The conception of jus 
divinum, divine law, is fundamental in Biblical thought. But if 
we try to formulate more clearly what this divine law is which 
so profoundly impresses us, particularly in the Old Testament, 
we are confronted with a series of most difficult and confusing 
questions. The jus divinum transcends all legal relations 
between men, being also the basis of purely moral and religious 
relations and conduct. In the Pauline concept of dikaiosyne 
Theou the element of divine mercy and forgiveness is essential, 
and the whole redemptive work of Christ is included. This 



108 SOCIAL CUSTOM ANd!) LAW [LECT. 

( 

new " righteousness " is the norm and essence of that relation 
between men which does not ask for jifeticelbut is based on 
spontaneous love, that love which Jesus fn the Sermon on the 
Mount opposes to the attitude dictated by mere justice. For the 
same reason it is impossible, though it has so often been tried, 
to make the Decalogue the basis for legal justice, because the 
Decalogue is interpreted by our Lord to mean nothing else 
than that free spontaneous love which transcends all require- 
ments of mere justice. And finally, the attempt to derive the 
divine law from the several codes of law in the Old Testament 
proves to be not very successful, because these laws were given 
to the people of Israel over more than a thousand years in its 
specific historical situation, which is so entirely different from 
ours. 

As a matter of fact, the development of law and legal practice 
in the Western Christian world has, on the whole, not followed 
the line of biblicism, but has tried to make the jus divinum bear 
upon the legal reality by the concept of jus naturale or lex 
naturae; or, more exactly, by identifying this concept of ancient 
philosophy and jurisprudence with the Christian idea of jus 
divinum. During fifteen centuries this jus naturale, in its 
Biblical or Christian interpretation, was the foundation of juri- 
dical thinking in Europe, until in the age of the Enlightenment 
the Christian interpretation was replaced by a rationalistic one, 
and, in the time of romantic historicism and naturalistic 
positivism, the whole idea of a jus naturale was abandoned, and 
jurisprudence and political theory became devoid of any kind of 
normative principle, law becoming a matter of mere political 
power. 

But this unfortunate development, resulting in the complete 
dissolution of the idea of natural law, had its origin — partly at 
least — in this concept itself, because from the beginning of its 
Christian history a double uncertainty or confusion was con- 
nected with it. First, it had never been made clear, either by 
theologians or by jurists, what was the distinction between the 
Christian and the pagan interpretation of lex naturae. Second, 
it had never become clear how lex naturae as the principle of 



VIIIJ |ATURAL LAW IO9 

juridical law was distinguished from Christian love as the prin- 
ciple of personal §condict. While it was certain that justice 
was not the same thftig as love, nobody seemed to be cap- 
able of giving a clear definition or a theological justification of 
justice as distinct from love. It is here that our thinking has 
to start. 

What is justice as distinct from love? And what is its 
theological foundation? Is there room for such justice within 
a Christian conception of God and of life? It is true that Jesus, 
laying down the rules of His kingdom, speaks of love only, 
calling it the " better righteousness More than that, He 
interprets this love in sharpest distinction from seeking one's 
own rights, and from legalism. He does not, however, teach 
His disciples not to respect the rights of others. The love which 
He teaches includes this respect for our neighbours' rights, 
while far transcending it. Love that would not first give the 
other man whatjie has a right to claim is mere sentimentality, 
and provokes resentment on the part of one's fellow man. 
While love is higher than mere justice, it is inclusive of justice. 
Love, then, presupposes justice. Because this is so, there must 
be a divine norm for this justice, which therefore is the basis 
also of all human law. What is this norm? 

Whoever says that a thing is just or unjust is thinking of 
something which belongs to man. Justice — in its distinction 
from love — is identical with "belonging", and this "belong- 
ing " is to be understood in a normative sense, independent of 
human laws. Justice presupposes a divine order of belonging, 
of whatever kind this belonging may be. This is the meaning 
of lex naturae, both in the pre-Christian and in the Christian 
sense. But within the Christian faith this order of belonging 
is not an order of "nature" — in the pantheistic sense of the word 
— but of God's creation. In creating anything, God gives it its 
own shape; He defines what belongs to its " Tightness In 
creating man, God says : " This and that belongs to man's life, 
this and that must not be taken away from man, but must be 
given to him. Man, whom I have created, has a claim to this 
and that, because I created him with this and that. To give it 



110 SOCIAL CUSTOM AN| LAW [LECT. 

to him is just; not to give it to him is unjust/' The basis of 
earthly justice, of legal order between m%i, isf God's creation of 
man, in so far as it includes those thing^f which belong to man 
and yet could, though unjustly, be taken away from him by his 
fellow men. In other words, the basis of the Christian con- 
ception of justice and law is the Christian conception of man. 

And this is, as a matter of fact, what has been for centuries 
the foundation of the Christian understanding of law and 
justice; it is still that where it has not been destroyed or per- 
verted by rationalism and — much worse — by naturalism and 
sceptical relativism. It is the Christian conception of man as a 
person, having from God's creation his divine origin and dignity, 
a person destined to have communion with other persons, ^a 
person-in-community. What distinguishes the legal structure 
of the " Christian " West from antiquity and from the rest of 
the world is this basic concept of person, this Biblical personal- 
ism. It hardly needs to be said that this Christian element has 
only been one of many which actually formed the laws and legal 
practices of the Western world. But even where it has not been 
dominant, it has still been effective as critical norm and standard. 

The mere fact that we speak of " man thus ignoring all 
differences of sex, age, race, class, etc., is a Christian heritage. 
In law this idea of " man as such " is of immediate practical 
importance, because it is on this idea that there rests what we' 
call " equal right When we read in our Swiss constitution — 
as probably in many others — " jeder Schweizer ist vor dem 
Gesetze gleich V this is a direct consequence or application of 
the Christian idea of man. Whatever may be the practical 
legal consequences drawn from this principle, it is in itself a 
factor of the first magnitude. 

It is closely related to a second idea which has exactly the 
same origin, the idea of " human rights It is only in quite 
recent years that we have rediscovered the necessity and bearing 
of this concept. By it we mean that there are things belonging 
to man as such, rights which precede the state, which the state 
has to acknowledge, but which it cannot create, " birthrights of 

1 All Swiss are equal before the law. 



VIIl] THE IDE^ OF <e HUMAN RIGHTS " III 

manhood " founded on God's creation. It is this conception 
which distinguishes th& lawful state from the totalitarian state. 
In the moment when Siese aboriginal human rights are denied 
or abolished by the staTe, the totalitarian state is there, at least 
in principle. That is why in the preceding parts of this lecture 
we have laid so much stress on the independence of law from 
the state. The human rights precede the state in order of 
dignity. The state is created for the protection of those human 
rights which man has not from the state but from the Creator. 

It is only fair to admit that this principle of human rights and 
of the conception of " man as man " has its roots not only in the 
Christian but also in the Stoic conception of man ; on that we 
d^elt in a lecture of the first series. The difference between 
the Stoic and Christian conceptions of " man as such however, 
becomes clear in the fact that in Christian anthropology man is 
not conceived of merely as an independent individual, but as a 
" person-in-comig.unity While Stoic and modern rationalism 
construed their philosophy of law and justice entirely from the 
standpoint of individual personality and therefore influenced 
the development of society in the direction of a thoroughgoing 
individualism, the Christian conception of man is characterised 
by a polarity of individual man and social community. There- 
fore the function of law is to safeguard not merely the rights of 
the individual, but at the same time those of the natural societies. 
Over against Stoic — or modern — individualism the Christian 
conception of justice stands for a communal personalism or, if 
you like, a personalistic socialism, in which the rights of the 
individual are limited by the rights of the community. 

On the other hand, this limitation of the individual by the 
community is entirely different from, and strictly opposed to, 
collectivist subordination of the individual, particularly under 
the state. The human person, and man's personal rights, are 
derived from the same source as those of the communities. The 
individual is not a mere function or functionary of the com- 
munity, of the state, but has his fundamental independence. In 
this respect the Christian conception of man, however different 
from individualistic liberalism, stands firm on the side of 



112 SOCIAL CUSTOM ANp LAW [LECI\ 

liberalism against all attempts of anonymous society or tyran- 
nical state to degrade the person into^a rqere instrument of 
collective power. t 

There is, however, an even deeper root of Christian opposition 
to all kinds of tyranny: the principle of divine sovereignty. 
The first pronouncement about " belongings " or " rights " is 
this: that all things belong to God. The jus divinum is not in 
the first place the right which God gives, but the right which 
God has, and this right alone is absolute. The phrase which we 
read at the beginning of books printed in Great Britain, " All 
rights reserved " is— in its most serious and literal sense — what 
the principle of the Divine Sovereignty means. By it all human 
rights are— if I may use this ugly word—de-absolutised. Wl$e 
they are given by God, they are nevertheless not absolute. This 
principle of God's sovereignty is the surest, and in fact the only, 
safeguard against two great dangers : a false absolutism of the 
sovereignty of the people, leading to anarchy, and a false 
absolutism of the sovereignty of the state, leading to totalitarian- 
ism. It is no chance, then, that in an age which has largely 
forgotten the meaning of the sovereignty of God, mankind is 
wavering between these two evils, anarchic dissolution of law 
and order, and tyrannical totalitarian order. 

The recognition of the sovereignty of God is, however, also a 
safeguard against a false absolutism of law itself. However 
firmly grounded these laws may be and must be, above all of 
them we read that inscription : " All rights reserved There is 
no absolute human justice. There is no absolute human law. 
Therefore we should not attempt what the rationalist philoso- 
phers of natural law attempted: to deduce from the first 
principles of justice a whole system of laws of timeless validity. 
Human life, as seen by the Christian, is characterised by twc 
traits which make .this impossible, its transitoriness and its 
sinfulness. What was just yesterday may be unjust to-morrow, 
because of changed conditions. What might be just for people 
who are " angels " may be thoroughly unjust for people who are 
sinners. There is no possibility of construing a perfect order of 
law and justice from a few given principles. 



VIIl] kEL ACTIVITY OF JUSTICE 113 

The mistrust of all over-systematic doctrines of law and justice 
is well grounded, and^ve praise the English for their instinct in 
this matter. But # thisfcharacter of English legal tradition, which 
to us Continentals islat the same time so confusing and so 
attractive, is immune against a most deadly relativism only by 
reason of the strong infiltration of the jus divinum of the 
Christian tradition, and by the fact that the Christian conception 
of man is still alive. 

There are two errors to be guarded against : deductive a priori 
constructions of systems, and relativistic opportunism. If we 
look back over the history of European law, we can observe 
quite distinctly that so long as Christian tradition was truly alive 
and dominant, there were no such systems of law as began to be 
developed by the rationalists of the 18th century. To-day, 
however, the second danger is much greater: that all divine 
foundation, norm, and sanction of law should disappear in the 
general trend of relativism and naturalism. The positivistic 
school of law, which has prevailed in Europe for almost a cen- 
tury, is largely responsible for the legal chaos and the totalitarian 
monstrosity. 

There is one last reason why we need a foundation of law in 
the jus divinum. Only where a glimmer of divine light shines 
through the legal order of a nation can spontaneous obedience 
be expected. Where the opinion becomes prevalent that law is 
nothing but human invention, a sum of decisions taken by 
political powers, or where the justice of the law disappears under 
an immensity of technical regulations, the people will not obey 
law spontaneously, but only because and in so far as they are 
afraid of enforcement. And where this condition prevails, 
more and more laws have to be made and more and more force 
must be used. We can escape the totalitarian state machinery 
only by the vigour of spontaneous obedience, and therefore only 
by a sense of the sacredness of the legal order. Happy that 
people which can count upon this attitude of free obedience; 
and woe to that people which has lost it. 



IX 



POWER 

AS the word "power" has many meanings, we want to 
/-% make plain from the start that by power we here under- 
-Z. A* stand the capacity of man to determine the life, i.e. the 
doing and the not-doing, of others, by compulsion. In a very 
strict sense, compulsion is impossible; even the mightiest and 
most cruel tyrant can compel no one to do his will, if the othfg 
man does not want to obey, but rather suffers the consequences 
of disobedience. In our time, however, scientific cruelty has 
brought us near the point where even this last resort of human 
freedom is eliminated. But in that case man as a human being 
is also eliminated and turned into an automaton. 

Apart from these two extremes, compulsion can be exerted by 
many means, and the sum of these available means we call 
power. A father can compel his children because they are 
dependent on him, or because he is physically stronger, or 
because his parental authority is granted by law and state. A 
teacher has power over his pupils, the " boss " has power over 
his employees, an officer over his men, a judge over the culprit. 
In a well-ordered state, the judge can be sure that the state will 
use all its means of compulsion in order to guarantee the carry- 
ing out of his sentence. The state has power over every single 
citizen and over every group of citizens. It can compel them to 
do what they do not like doing. The great powers amongst the 
nations are those that can, if they wish, subjugate the small ones 
to their will, either directly or indirectly. To have power does 
not necessarily mean to use it, though its mere existence has an 
effect similar to its actual use wherever it is uncertain how this 
power will be used. 

Power over others is desired by most men for two reasons. 
First, power over another man is, so to say, a reduplication of 



AN ESSENTIAL DEFINITION II5 

! 

one's own existence. Instead of one, I have two human 
organisms at my disposal. I can make the other work and live 
for me without worryii 1g about his life beyond his utility for me. 
The second reason is u£ a more inward nature. Power means 
also enhancement of value, prestige, whether in my own esti- 
mation or in that of others. We therefore understand why men 
desire power, and why few who have it abstain from using it, 
whether in the first, more objective, or in the second, more 
subjective, sense. 

Power is the more desirable as the goods of this world are 
already portioned out, because by power this distribution can be 
changed in favour of the one who has power. That is why a 
lajge part of human life is a struggle for power or the use of 
power in the struggle for goods. This power and its use can 
take various shapes. Everything by which the capacity to 
compel is increased can become a means of power: bodily 
strength and ability, shrewdness in putting one's own superiority 
into action in t&e right place, possession of things that others 
must have or desire to have ,* and these things can be of the most 
different kinds : economic goods, the keys of Heaven or doors to 
the high places in society or state. It is impossible to separate 
physical power from spiritual, even with regard to compulsion. 
The power of the state, for instance, by which it can compel the 
citizens, is not merely, nor even predominantly, the police and 
military force which stand behind its commands ; it is composed 
of innumerable factors, the sum of which may be called the 
spiritual authority of the state. 

Because power is the capacity to compel, it stands in direct 
opposition to freedom. The power of one over the other is the 
dependence of the second on the first. Power and freedom are 
related as the convex to the concave. The surplus of freedom 
of the one, which is power, is the deficit of freedom of the other. 
Power creates dependence. But not all dependence is created by 
power, because there exists also dependence out of free will. 
Furthermore, a dependence created by power may become 
spontaneous. The good citizen of a good state wants the state 
to be powerful. He accepts its compulsive power with his free 

1 



Il6 POWER [LECT. 

will. The freely chosen leader of a group has power which the 
group accepts and which therefore is not felt as compulsion. 
This freely willed power must not be a nfused with a merely 
psychic dependence or bondage, which is a strange mixture of 
acceptance and refusal of power. 

Because power, taken by itself, is opposed to freedom, there is 
a tendency in every society to order and to canalise power in 
order to limit its danger for the less powerful. The most im- 
portant means to order power is law, which in itself is nothing 
but " ordered power " or " order of power It is a necessity of 
civilised life that the ultimate use of power, the power over the 
lives of others, be centralised. This centralisation of ultimate 
power is the state. It originates from the necessity to locafoe 
ultimate power in a few hands and to canalise it by certain rules. 
What we call state is the centralised monopoly of exerting ulti- 
mate power. Power, not merely social organisation, is the 
characteristic essence of the state. The social organisation oi 
society is in itself something very " harmless The state, how- 
ever, begins at the moment when this harmlessness disappears 
i.e. when behind this social organisation an institution stands 
with ultimate power, power over men's lives. This instrument 
the state, is necessary as a safeguard of peace because it is onlj 
this monopoly of ultimate power that checks the tendency oi 
men to use their powers to the utmost limit for their own benefit 
up to the point of killing. The will-to-power, and recklessness ir 
using it are so strong in man that again and again he does no- 
hesitate to kill. Until this possibility is taken away by th< 
monopoly of ultimate power by the state, peaceful civilised lifi 
cannot develop. In this sense the state is the presupposition o: 
cultural life. 

This centralisation of ultimate power in the state, however, i 
only one step in taming the dangerous power-element. Th< 
second step is the ordering of centralised power by law. Ulti 
mate power and the power of the state in general must be exertec 
only within definite limits, and for definite purposes, and in * 
definite manner. The power of the state should only be usee 
in the service of the life of the people and in defence of thei 



1X1 PUBLIC AND PRIVATE LAW H7 

rights. The state must be the guarantee of peace, order and 
justice. We have^ see*| in the preceding lecture that the state is 
not the source of law, i|>ut rather its guarantee. The state is the 
servant of man and ilot their master. Its raison d'etre is to 
protect the lives and the rights of men. That is why the mono- 
poly of ultimate power is given to it. State-law is primarily law 
for the state and not law of the state. State-law is the limitation 
and canalisation of the power of the state. We call it public 
law, in distinction from private law, which the power of the 
state has to protect. It is by public law that society orders and 
disciplines the dangerous, though necessary, power of the state 
which is monopolised ultimate power. The rights of individuals 
a»d their lawful relations are not created by the state, but they 
are publicly acknowledged and protected by the coercive power 
of the state. 

A third step, however, is necessary in order to guarantee this 
purpose of the^tate. This third step is the plurality of the 
bearers of power in the state what we call the division of power. 
This was the meaning in creating parliament, and this also was 
the meaning of a much older institution : courts independent o£ 
government. The absolute monarch united all state functions 
in his person. He was ruler, law-giver and judge. Yet the 
principle of " division of powers " is much older than Montes- 
quieu ; Montesquieu was merely the first who clearly recognised 
its importance. Already in the people of Israel there existed 
a certain division of powers; law was not given by the king, 
but by God through prophets and priests, and the king had to 
obey and to protect this law. The Roman Republic represents 
a well-thought-out division of powers, which was the result of 
century-long struggles. Montesquieu's principle, le pouvoir 
arrete le pouvoir, is the most essential element of a constitutional 
state, as distinct from absolutism and tyranny. 

Whilst it would not be true to the facts to claim that the 
conception of power set forth in the preceding pages is ex- 
clusively Christian, it certainly is deeply rooted in the Christian 
faith. The sovereignty of God excludes an absolute of human 
power. It excludes both the absolute sovereignty of the 



Il8 POWER [LEGT. 

state and the absolute sovereignty of the people. All human 
sovereignty is limited by divine sovereignty ajnd by divine law. 
Furthermore, the Christian conception' of sin reveals the 
dangers inherent in power. The Christian knows better than 
anyone else the temptation to misuse which is inherent in great 
power. Power is misused wherever it is used against the law of 
God and contrary to its God-given purpose. 

When St. Paul deduces the power of the state from^divine 
order and enjoins Christians to obey it, he is not thinking of the 
absolute sovereignty of state or monarch. The divine origin of 
the power of the state (exousia) is at the same time divir&j limita- 
tion. According to St. Paul this limitation is given with the 
purpose of the state, which is peace and justice. In stressing tfe 
power of the sword as a means of divine vengeance St. Paul 
gives that interpretation of the state as monopolised ultimate 
power which we have just been sketching. By this reference to 
the power of the sword the state is not reduced to the police 
function as has often been said. This reference to the sword is 
rather an expression of Biblical realism with regard to the basic 
elements of the state. It shows that the monopoly of ultimate 
power is the very essence of the state, as a basis for peaceful 
civilised life. This conception of state and power is correlative 
with the Biblical conception of sin. Wherever the power of sin 
and the temptation to sin, inherent in power, is seen, it becomes 
impossible to regard the state as a mere social organisation, as 
is done on the basis of an optimistic view of the nature of man. 

The need for the concentration and canalisation of power in 
the state is so much the greater as there are great accumulations 
of power within society. Society does not consist of individuals 
merely, but of groups, some of which wield tremendous power. 
In our capitalist age there are concentrations of financial and 
industrial power, compared with which the individual is power- 
less. The credit system, combined with industrialisation, has 
produced an accumulation of economic power unknown in 
previous times : " big business mammoth corporations con- 
trolling billions of dollars and hundreds of thousands of men, 
capable of limiting their freedom in a large measure, dominating 



IX] THE PAULINE DOCTRINE 1 19 

the" economic life and welfare of whole nations, and influencing 
the state machinery i#l a dangerously high degree. By theijr 
more or less monopolistic character, they exert an almost 
state-like coercive powir. 

This, however, is only one side of the picture. On the other 
side we see accumulations of power created by organisation of 
those who individually are powerless, i.e. the ever-growing power 
of trade unions and trade-union associations which in some 
countries has become equal to that of their capitalistic counter- 
parts. Experience has proved that the great numbers of men 
associated in an organisation are at least equal in power to great 
wealth and, in the long run, even superior. By the development 
o£»these two concentrations of power, a new danger originates. 
These colossi, both business corporations and trade-union 
federations, have become, so to say, states within the state, 
being capable of challenging the state and thereby endangering 
its primary purpose. The purpose of the state is to serve the 
interests of all. Those economic mammoth organisations, 
however, are so powerful that they are able to force the state 
to do their will against public welfare. This situation explains 
in part why so many are intent upon strengthening the economic 
power of the state and are calling for a general state-control and 
even nationalisation of economy. 

The last decades, however, have confronted us with a pheno- 
menon more dangerous than any other to freedom and general 
welfare: the totalitarian state. The more comprehensive the 
state, the more dangerous its power. The democratic and 
liberal movement sprang from the desire to combat the danger 
that lay in state absolutism at a time when state absolutism was 
represented by the absolute monarch. Parliament and constitu- 
tional government were an efEective attempt to bridle it. Since 
then monarchy has either disappeared or been eliminated as the 
bearer of power. Since the French Revolution the democratic 
principle of the " sovereignty of the people " has conquered the 
Western world. The rise of the totalitarian state — beginning 
in 1917 — created a new situation. It is only now that we are 
beginning to see that the sovereignty of the people, manifesting 



120 POWER [LECT. 

itself in the election of the government by the people, is not in 
itself a safe guarantee against a new kimd of state absolutism. 
It is possible to conceive a totalitarian /'state on a democratic 
basis. To think of democracy and totalitarianism as opposites 
is just as wrong as to identify totalitarianism with dictatorship. 
State-totalitarianism is not a form of government. The form of 
a state decides how and by whom political power is to be wielded. 
Totalitarianism, however, means die extension of political power 
over the totality of life whatever may be the form of govern- 
ment. The nationalisation of economy is the decisive step to 
this totality of political control over the totality of life. If 
neither individuals nor groups have independent economic 
means, they do not have real political freedom. If everyone ira 
functionary of the state, and if nobody can make his living in- 
dependently of the state machinery, if there are no other than 
state schools, if the press, the cinema, the radio, are state con- 
trolled, free society is lost, opposition and public expression 
of independent opinion become impossible. Every deviation 
from the programme of the state becomes rebellion and sabotage. 
Even if this state has a democratic form, i.e. government 
elected by the majority vote of the people, it amounts to a 
complete suppression of liberty, and it will not be long before 
even the so-called free elections become illusory, the state 
machinery controlling all means of propaganda. 

Compared with this modern totalitarian state, the absolute 
monarchy of old times looks rather innocent, because even under 
the most absolute monarch private property of individuals and 
groups, and the absence of state-controlled education and public 
opinion, left a considerable area open for free decision. In the 
totalitarian state, however, this area of free decision hardly 
exists, and therefore a free development of cultural life is almost 
totally excluded. For cultural self-expression is dependent on 
material means, and all these material means are in the hands 
of the state. To take one example : if the state decides who is 
to get the paper available for printing, can we believe that an 
opposition press could exist? The totalitarian state even con- 
trols the time of every individual citizen. No one can say : I 



IX] MODERN ABSOLUTISM 121 

prefer to earn less in order to have time for this or that cultural, 
moral or religious activity. State economy can exist only if it 
has complete control of the working time of everybody. 
Furthermore, it is the Itate that dictates for what things money 
may be or may not be spent. It not only controls schools and 
universities, but also the schools and exhibitions of art, and the 
theatre, all artists and actors being state employees. While in 
theory it is not forbidden to do, apart from matters of national 
importance, whatever one likes, this theoretical freedom is 
illusory, because it is the state alone which has the financial 
means necessary for any cultural activity. All this means that 
totalitarianism, even in a democratic form, is the grave of 
feaedom. 

Furthermore, even a democratic totalitarian state must 
necessarily degenerate because its power is unlimited. It 
produces an all-powerful bureaucracy of functionaries and a 
semi-militaristic^ hierarchy. This hierarchy necessarily has a 
monarchical top. The principle of the division of power 
becomes illusory. Its place is taken by the rivalry of the 
different sections of the state machinery, but all of them are 
dependent on the self-same pinnacle of the bureaucratic 
hierarchy. The democratic drama will still be played while 
actually there is a tyrannical dictatorship. All this is not 
merely a description of one of the totalitarian systems of the 
present time : these things are all the necessary and inevitable 
results of the complete nationalisation of economy. We have 
seen in recent years how — whether we like it or not — a war-time 
economy produces almost necessarily the worst features of 
totalitarianism : secret police, administrative jurisdiction, control 
of public opinion, etc., and that even within states with deeply 
rooted democratic tradition and with democratic institutions 
intact, complete state control of economy leads to the militarisa- 
tion of the life of a nation. 

For all these reasons the totalitarian state, being the absolute 
maximum of accumulated power, is the worst and most dan- 
gerous social evil which we can conceive. It is the Satanic 
incarnation of our time. Whatever analogies totalitarianism 



122 POWER [lECT, 

may have had in previous centuries, real totalitarianism has 
become possible only in our age, in which £he techniques of 
production and transport, the aeroplane, the radio and the 
machine-gun, have made state power omnipresent, all-powerful 
and all-pervasive. 

We have now to turn to a last and no less gloomy aspect of the 
power problem: the power-relation between the states. Man- 
kind has somehow succeeded in eliminating the most destructive 
effects of power within a given territory by concentrating 
ultimate power in the state. Man has succeeded furthermore 
in bridling the state-power itself by law and constitutional 
division of power. In recent times, however, the formation of 
a few powerful states has created a new problem : the struggle 
for power between the major states, endangering the life and 
freedom of humanity. Thus far all attempts to bring the 
power-relations of the states under the control of justice and 
humanitarian interests have been almost without effect. 

It may be said that in times when the divine law and the 
moral order exerted considerable influence on the nations and 
their rulers, this purely spiritual limitation of power exerted a 
certain smoothing and muffling influence. The states, however 
ruthless in their international behaviour, did not quite do every- 
thing lying within their power. By treaties they created a kind 
of international law, which proved effective to a certain extent, 
although its effects were limited by the fact that the treaties 
could not be enforced. For this reason modern man created 
institutions of international justice and peace, like the Court of 
the Hague, and the League of Nations, which were intended to 
replace the use of power by law. These institutions, however, 
proved incapable of solving the most important and dangerous 
conflicts arising from the dynamic character of history because 
they were limited by the principle of the sovereignty of the 
individual states. The League of Nations was certainly an 
attempt to limit individual state sovereignty by a supra-national 
federal structure. But this attempt proved futile because the 
great powers did not really intend to abandon their sovereignty 
to the will of the federation, and because some of the most 



IX] INTERNATIONAL ANARCHY 123 

powerful states were not members of the League. Horrified by 
the disastrous results of the second world war, the nations made 
a second attempt m the same direction by forming the United 
Nations Organisation. t Although only a few years have elapsed 
since its formation, it must be admitted that this second attempt 
has also failed for the present. A condition of international 
anarchy therefore still prevails, leaving the feeble nation at the 
mercy ^of the powerful, and threatening humanity with a new 
conflagration which, should it become a reality, would most 
probably mean the end of human civilisation. 

There remains the question of a world state. Why should it 
not be possible to overcome world-wide international anarchy 
ir&a way similar to that in which it has been overcome within a 
given territory by the little Swiss or by the big American 
federation, which combine regional autonomy with the over- 
arching supremacy of the federation? Apart from the fact that 
such a proposals purely academic for the present and for the 
near future, the question remains whether such a universal world 
state, having the monopoly of ultimate power, would not be the 
greatest danger to freedom and higher culture. Only a federal 
structure, combined with a strict division of powers, would 
prevent it from degenerating into tyranny. A centralised non- 
federative, or, if I may use the phrase, a monolithic, world state 
would necessarily become a monster power of totalitarian 
character, whereas a federal structure always involves a certain 
risk for the peace of the world. 

A truly Christian solution of the power problem, in either its 
economic, political or international aspect, does not seem to be a 
realistic prospect. The idea of a reign of peace and justice, in 
which the lust for power would not only be tamed, but be over- 
come from within, cannot materialise in a world of sinful men. 
There are not a few who do believe in such an earthly paradise. 
Probably they do not realise that such a hope implies one of two 
things. Either they have to assume that within this temporal 
world sin, that is lust for power, can be overcome, or they do 
not see that real peace is irreconcilable with sin. Both these 
views contradict the Christian conception of man and history. 



124 POWER [LEGT. 

Because as Christians we see the close connection between power 
and sin, we accept St. Paul's idea that only by monopolised 
ultimate power, i.e. by the state, can sinful" anarchy be overcome. 
Whether it will be possible at some time to overcome the 
anarchy between the powerful states themselves by subordinat- 
ing them to a super-power without endangering justice and 
freedom, we cannot know, though we may hope for it. 

A short word may be added about the relation between power 
and culture. We cannot follow Jakob Burckhardt, who in his 
Weltgeschichtliche Betrachtungen opposes power to culture and 
makes culture, so to speak, the innocent martyr of power. How 
often has it happened that the most generous patrons of science 
and art have been also most ruthless in their power politks, 
misusing their power. It is not culture, it is only respect for 
justice, love, and reverence for the divine law, that are capable 
of overcoming the lust for and the misuse of power. It is only 
that mind which would rather suffer an injustice than perform 
it, and which is willing to " overcome evil with good that is 
capable of resisting the temptation even of very great power. 
The greater the power, the greater the temptation of being god- 
like. Against this temptation no education or culture can 
prevail. The demon of power is overcome only by Jesus Christ. 
Therefore the most important thing that can be done at any 
rime against the evil effects of the power motive is the spreading 
and deepening of true Christ-discipleship. The most dreadful 
thing, however, is the will-to-power in a Christian disguise, of 
which Western history is full. It is here, if anywhere, that we 
can see the cunning of the devilish power taking the shape of an 
angel of light, and thereby hiding the One who alone is capable 
of driving out the spirit of power. 

We started our discussion with a definition of power, limiting 
its meaning to " the capacity to compel We said that this 
use of the word was not the only possible one. We speak now of 
power in a sense which is far removed from this one. The 
multiplicity of meanings is not a matter of mere chance. Power 
in the most general sense is that which is capable of moving, 
particularly of moving us human creatures. There is a kind of 



% 

IX] OVERCOMING EVIL WITH GOOD 125 

power which moves us not by compulsion but by conviction. 
An idea may prove powerful— idee force. Such power, while it 
moves us, does not impinge upon our free action. On the con- 
trary, such power makls us free. As Christians we speak of the 
power of God moving us by His spirit of truth and holy love. 
The apostles preached the gospel of Christ as the saving power 
of the world, as that power which beyond all others makes man 
free, giving him and revealing to him the truth of his own being, 
creating him as a free personality. 

Christianity has proved a power in history. The gospel 
moved men to do what had never been done before and to refrain 
from doing what had always been done before ; it moved them 
tomiS.tr and to love, to rise above the level of the all-too-human 
and yet to remain human, nay, to become truly human by love 
and obedience to the divine will. Wherever the Christian faith 
in its New Testament purity has been present in individuals, in 
groups, in peopjf s, new things have happened, by the power of 
God. The greatest proof of this power of God is that it over- 
comes the lust for power, and thereby becomes a genuinely new 
factor in political life. Whether this happens very often or not 
is not the immediate question. We know, both from the teach- 
ing of the New Testament and from Christian experience, that 
wherever Christian faith is alive this does happen, sometimes 
in a lesser, sometimes in a higher, and sometimes in the 
highest and most conspicuous degree. And this is therefore the 
one bright feature in the picture : that Christian faith, love of 
God, and love of one's fellow man, does act as a political factor 
inasmuch as it works against the misuse of political power and 
works for that use of political power which is for the common 
good. It is natural, it is even inevitable, for Christians to hope 
that the influence of this Christian motive may become so great 
that solutions of political power problems which otherwise are 
insoluble become possible. 

In the field of political action — which is a field of dynamics — 
numbers count, and therefore combination of human wills for 
concerted action counts. The Christian community or Church 
has in itself a principle of community inseparable from Christian 



126 POWER 

faith. It has therefore a chance in the political field — in the 
field of " power in the first sense of the word — to influence the 
course of history, provided that it is pure, strong and united. 
If it is not pure, it will become powerful ki the had sense of the 
word, and will lust for that power ; if it is not strong, it cannot 
compete in the field where power is decisive; if it is not united, 
it has little chance to influence the political course of history. 
There is no reason to deny the possibility that the Christian 
faith, in its original purity and unity and strength, mighf again 
become such a reality that it could change the gloomy picture of 
the political scene. There is every reason for Christians to pray 
and to work that this may happen, because unless it does happen 
it is most probable that the prospects of our civilisation wll 
become gloomier still. 



X 



THE CHRISTIAN IDEA OF CIVILISATION AND 
CULTURE 

WfE have spoken so far, in the first series of these lectures, 
about the foundation of civilisation, and in the earlier 
lectures* of this series about some spheres of civilised 
or cultural life. We now go back to the question with which we 
started: what is a Christian civilisation? We have seen how 
problematic this concept is. We have stated that there never 
was in a strict sense a Christian civilisation, and that what is 
usually called by that name is a compromise between Christian 
and non-Christian forces. We have now come to the point where 
it may be possible to sketch something like the Christian idea of 
civilisation or culture. By the two terms, civilisation and 
culture, we understand something typically and exclusively 
human; man alone is capable of producing it. Whatever 
astonishing analogies may be found in the life of animals — the 
beaver-dam, the state of the ants, the so-called language and 
games of the animals — they are mere analogies and not begin- 
nings of cultured and civilised life because they are all tied to 
biological necessities, as nourishment, procreation and shelter. 
Man alone can transcend these necessities by his creative 
imagination, and by the idea of something which is not yet but 
ought to be; by the ideas of the good, of justice, beauty, perfec- 
tion, holiness and infinitude. It is true that even human 
civilisation and culture are related to biological necessity and 
have their basis within natural organic life which is common to 
us and the animals. But even where man is tied to biological 
necessity he acts in a way which transcends mere utility and 
gives his doings a human stamp. He does not " feed " like the 
animals, he eats; he ornaments his vessels, his instruments, his 
house, he establishes and observes fine customs, he explores 

127 



128 CHRISTIAN CIVILISATION AND CULTURE [LECT. 

truth irrespective of utility, he creates beautiful things for the 
sheer joy of beauty. He orders his relations according to ideas 
of justice and liberty. He masters power by law, he sacrifices 
time, energy and life for ideas and ideals. All this is civilisa- 
tion and culture. Therefore we can define them as that 
formation of human life which has its origin not in mere 
biological necessity but in spiritual impulses. Wherever spirit, 
transcending the physical urge, enters the scene of life as a 
formative force, there civilisation and culture comes into 
existence. t 

These spiritual impulses and formative forces *are of the most 
varied kinds. The impulse to create the beautiful, to realise 
justice, to know the truth, to preserve the past, to enter i*ito 
spiritual communication, to invent the new, to extend the range 
of human intercommunion, to share the sufferings and joys of 
others; the impulse to submit the totality of life to ultimate 
directives and give it a meaning, unity and intelligibility, and 
finally to place everything under the divine will and receive it 
from the hands of God — all these are impulses out of which 
culture and civilisation arise. 

All the same, we should not idealise culture and civilisation, 
as is done so often. These spiritual motives, although trans- 
cending biological necessity, are mixed with egoism, lust for 
power, and ambition. They are in competition with each other, 
one motive trying to displace the others and to monopolise life. 
Artistic or scientific impulses can be mixed with irresponsi- 
bility, inhuman hardness and brutality. The scientist can be 
blind to art, the artist to science, and both can be indifferent to 
moral ox religious truth. Religion can become fanatical and 
cruel, it can hamper or even cripple art, science, technics, com- 
munity, by its prejudices. Although all these spiritual elements 
transcend the biological urge, none of them as such is a guar- 
antee of true, full humanity. Everyone of them can become a 
parasite in relation to the others, or an idol, or a caricature. 
The intensity and height of cultural achievement therefore is 
no sure mark of a truly human life. Intensity can be in conflict 
with harmony or totality. And this conflict can assume the 



s 

X] SPIRITUAL ESSENTIALS 129 

most evil and ugliest forms of the struggle for life. Spiritual 
energy, combined with lust for power and egoism, gives, the 
animal instincts 5 demoniac power unknown in the animal 
realm. The means wl^ich technics and organisation, planning 
and association, give to the human will, can produce a kind o£ 
civilisation which, although it is still characteristic of man, can 
lead into catastrophes that may amount to a suicide of humanity. 

All these dark aspects belong to the character of human 
civilisation, which is the civilisation of sinful men. Civilisation 
and culture, then, are not in themselves the opposite of evil and 
depravity. They can become the very instruments of evil and 
negative forces, as they have always been to a certain extent. 
Culture and civilisation, although they belong exclusively to 
man, are not in themselves the truly human. True, without 
culture and civilisation man cannot be human, but in them- 
selves they do not guarantee the truly human character of life. 
That is what we have called, in a previous connection, the formal 
character of civilisation. Wherever spirit expresses itself, there 
is civilised life; but what kind of a spirit creates that civilisation 
or culture is another question. Culture is an expression of the 
spirit, a formation by spiritual impulse, but this spiritual impulse 
can originate from the most different sources, and therefore is 
no guarantee of inner unity. 

The question then arises whether there exists a spiritual 
impulse capable of relating all the other impulses in the right 
proportions and unifying them in such a way as to produce a 
truly human life. Does there exist an understanding of man 
which gives to all the elements of human life — the biological, 
economic, technical, scientific, artistic, individual, social and 
communal — their full chance, and which at the same time 
subdues all of them to that which guarantees true humanity? 
Furthermore, is this understanding of man, if it exists, of such 
a kind that it is capable of functioning as an organising dynamic, 
so that it is not a mere idea but a directing power? As a result 
of our investigations we can give a positive answer to these 
questions. This conception of man is implicit in the Christian 
faith in its New Testament purity and dynamic. 



130 CHRISTIAN CIVILISATION AND CULTURE j_LECT. 

The Christian faith alone views man as a spiritual-bodily unit 
whose powers and impulses, originating from his physical nature 
and from his spiritual disposition, are all co-ordinated in such a 
way that they are subordinated to a huowi destiny which trans- 
cends both the natural and the spiritual life, and is directive of 
both. " All are yours, and ye are Christ's, and Christ is God's/' 
"Of every tree of the garden thou mayest freely eat" — only 
from the tree in the middle of the garden, the tree of the divine 
mystery, by reservation of the holy God, man shall not eat. All 
that is creature is in a specific way subordinated to man, but he 
himself with all his life and powers is subordinated to God who 
is holy love and who destines men for communion with Himself 
and with each other. Man is created to subdue and l^gLve 
dominion over all creation, but " whether you eat or drink or 
whatsoever you do, do all to the glory of God This is the 
programme of life given to men by the Creator : free develop- 
ment of all their powers, free use of all the means under the 
dominion of the One who grves all and ordains all to Himself. 

Now, before we go on to enlarge this Biblical idea of culture, 
some questions have to be taken up which obtrude themselves 
from the standpoint of history. As we have seen, in our first 
lecture, the New Testament shows very little interest in the 
specific tasks of civilisation and culture. How then can faith, 
which seems so indifferent to culture, be its basis? Our answer 
is twofold. First, it is true that the main concern of* the New 
Testament message is not culture or civilisation, not the tem- 
poral but the eternal, not the earthly but the heavenly life. 
The Gospel is not f ocussed on culture, but on the world-to-come. 
" This world passes away and with it civilisation. Christian 
faith, indeed, is alive only where the life with God in Christ and 
the eternal kingdom of God is the centre of interest. " Seek ye 
first His kingdom and His righteousness." The kingdom of 
God is not human civilisation. It stands above both the physical 
and the cultural life. That is the first thing which has to be 
said. The second point, however, which must be repeated, is 
that this perspective of the kingdom of God does not alienate 
men from their temporal life. Faith in the kingdom and in 



x] t5e means and the end 131 

eternal life does not make men indifferent to the tasks which 
earthly existence lays upon them. On the contrary, the 
Christian is sumrr^ned to tackle them with special energy, and 
his faith gives him the j>ower to solve these problems better than 
he could without faith. " Seek ye first the kingdom of God 
. . . and these things shall be added unto you." It is precisely 
the man whose first concern is not culture but the kingdom of 
God that has the necessary distance from cultural aims and 
the necessary perspective to serve them in freedom, and to grasp 
that order which prevents the various sections of civilisation 
from monopolising the totality of life. Only from beyond 
civilisation can its order and harmony come. 

It is a humanistic superstition to believe that the man to 
whom culture is everything is the true bearer of culture. The 
opposite is true. Culture necessarily degenerates where it is 
made God. Culture-idolatry is the sure road to cultural decay. 
If culture is to become and to remain truly human, it must have 
a culture-transc&iding centre. Man is more than his culture. 
Culture is means and tool, but not the essence of human life. 
It is not culture that gives man his humanity, but it is the 
human man that creates a human culture. That is why it is a 
grave error to think that the Christian faith is the enemy of 
culture, or at least indifferent to it, because it so emphatically 
accentuates the culture-transcending centre of life. 

But what is the verdict of history? I think that, correcdy 
interpreted, it confirms what has just been said. It is true that 
there have been Christian movements showing a kind of cultural 
asceticism, that there have been times when faith and theological 
interest absorbed men to such a degree that they neglected their 
cultural obligations. It is true that the Christian Church has 
sometimes obstructed the development of science or other 
cultural functions. While we are not justified in taking these 
negative facts too lightly, we are obliged on the other hand to 
beware of rash inferences. We have always to make sure first 
whether it is really Christian faith that acts, and secondly 
whether it is really cultural values that are at stake. In 
Occidental history so many things have usurped the name of 

K 



132 CHRISTIAN CIVILISATION AND CULTURE [LECT. 

" Christian " which were only half Christian or pseudo- 
Christian. On the other hand, so many things have been postu- 
lated in the name of cultural necessity that we?e pseudo-cultural. 
Because it is of the nature of sin that one branch of life wants to 
develop at the cost of another equally important, and because it 
is a temptation for the cultured man to idolise culture and 
thereby deprive it of its truly human character, it must always 
be the foremost interest of the Christian to proclaim faith and 
love as the source and norm of all true humanity. By doing 
this, he does, in the long run, the best service to culture. 

Finally, there is always a certain tendency in cultural human- 
ism to understand spirit and culture in such a way that so-called 
" higher " culture becomes detached from every-day life, from 
marriage and family, from civic order and from social oblfga- 
tions. Such a humanism is inclined to forget that the soundness 
of family life is the basis of all true civilisation, that justice and 
freedom in public life are necessary presuppositions of all higher 
culture. There is a certain aristocracy of spiriC which has little 
interest in popular education, or in the task of giving a real 
meaning to the work of the ordinary man, and which focusses 
all its interest on science, art and so-called higher culture. Such 
an attitude proves detrimental to real culture. It is at this point 
that the importance of the Christian view of life becomes parti- 
cularly obvious. All this makes the question of the relations 
between historical Christianity and civilisation so complicated 
that it is hardly possible to reach a final judgment. On one 
point, however, we can speak without reserve: the history of 
civilisation during the last hundred years has made clear beyond 
any doubt that the progressive decline of Christian influence has 
caused a progressive decay of civilisation. But even that may 
remain doubtful to one who personally has no understanding of 
what Christian faith means. 

These preliminaries being settled, we can now proceed to 
develop a little further the Christian idea of culture and civilisa- 
tion. We start from the statement that human culture 
presupposes human man. It is not culture that makes man 
human, but it is human man who makes culture human. This 



X] DIVINE AND HUMAN RELATIONS I33 

order of things is given with the Christian faith. Man comes 
first, not civilised life. Man becomes human, not by cukure 
and civilisation, b&t by understanding his human destiny. In 
the Christian revelation the destiny of man is love. The measure 
of culture is personality; more exactly, person-in-communion. 
Creative individuality is no equivalent of personal life in com- 
munity. God is love — that is the centre of the Christian 
message, and this doctrine is exclusively Christian. Love is the 
first and the last, the ultimate reality, being the very essence of 
God. Love is not one amongst others, not one virtue alongside 
other virtues ; love is no virtue at all : it is true humanity, as it 
is the essence of God. This love, agape in the New Testament 
sen^e, is no natural disposition. It is acquired by faith. Man is 
created for this love : that is why he has a longing for it. But 
in spite of this natural longing, man does not have it by birth, 
he has to receive it as a supernatural gift. By this, his eternal 
destiny, man is ^ulture-transcending. The meaning of his life 
is not in culture; on the contrary, it is his task to express and to 
realise this culture-transcending destiny in his cultural life. 
Culture then is means, expression, tool of true humanity, but 
not its origin and aim. 

The first consequence of this conception of life is that the 
most important thing in life is the relation between man and 
man. Therefore it is not impersonal spiritual activity, it is not 
spiritual creation as such, but it is the formation of truly per- 
sonal social relationships, which is the basis of true culture. 
There is more real culture in a truly human family life without 
art and science than in the highest achievements of art and 
science on the basis of neglected family life and degenerate 
sex-relations. 

The second consequence of Christian anthropology is the 
acknowledgment of man's bodily-spiritual unity. In contrast 
with idealistic humanism, Christian faith does not despise the 
body and the bodily needs. The Christian doctrine of incarna- 
tion obliges the Christian to take the body and its needs 
seriously, and gives him the double task of incorporating the 
spirit and spiritualising the bodily life. Spirituality detached 



134 CHRISTIAN CIVILISATION AND CULTURE [LECT. 

from the concerns of the body contradicts the Biblical doctrine 
of creation and produces an abstract kind of culture. The 
Christian understanding of corporal-spiritual unity has two 
consequences. First, it places the body r under the direction of 
the spirit. Second, it takes seriously the problems of manual 
work, economy and material property. From this point of view 
a decent and meaningful order of every-day life and healthy 
economic conditions are important criteria of true civilisation. 
A well-ordered estate, with dignified houses of simple* beauty 
and a carefully-managed farm, is a surer indication of true 
culture than a marvellous university, a famous academy of art, 
in the midst of a peasant or industrial proletariat. The Christian 
ethos has — paradoxical as this may appear — a strongly bourgeois 
trait, if we understand this word in its original sense of well- 
ordered citizenship. In the New Testament, eschatology — 
which certainly is the very opposite of anything bourgeois — is 
combined with a sober and earnest ethic of work and an 
intention to equalise social conditions. One might say with 
Kierkegaard, that this bourgeois element is the necessary 
outward incognito of the essentially anti-boufgeois heart and 
mind of the Christian. 

The primacy of personal relations, as distinguished from 
purely abstract spiritual creativity, has another important 
consequence. In the Christian conception of sin it is not sensu- 
ality but egoism and pride which hold the first place. That is 
why those dangers which come from lust of power are taken 
most seriously, and why a high premium is placed upon good 
government and public justice. Social relations cannot be in 
accordance with human dignity if this lust for power is not 
kept within firm barriers in economic as well as in political life. 
To lead a truly human life, man must have an intangible sphere 
of freedom guaranteed by law. For this reason the Christian 
must regard civic order, security, and a certain homogeneity in 
the sphere of economics, as an important criterion of cultural 
soundness. Wherever public institutions give evidence of the 
will to form human life as a community of free personalities, 
there is culture. 



X] TRADITION AND EDUCATION 135 

From the same source derives the high valuation of tradition 
and social custom. These conservative forces, which limfc the 
freedom of the Individual, however, are not without strong 
counter-weights, origii&ating from the Christian hope of a new 
world. It may be said, perhaps, that in the Christian view of a 
good life the conservative elements are stressed so much because 
otherwise the eschatological perspective of the Christian faith 
might lead to an illusionist revolutionary attitude. On the 
other fciand, tradition and social custom are an expression of the 
sense of responsibility and mutual obligation. They represent 
the element of •solidarity and loyalty, helping the individual — if 
they are not stressed too much — to acquire mature independence. 

Qne of the most obvious contributions of Christianity to 
civilised life is its pre-eminent interest in education and instruc- 
tion. Again, the Christian view of education is characterised by 
its personalism. It is not knowledge and ability which stand in 
the first rank, but education of responsible personality and social 
training. Wherever Christian tradition has been alive, it has 
influenced the educational life of the nations in this direction. 
In contrast with'it, the dechristianisation of Continental Europe, 
as the result first of an abstract spiritualism of a humanistic type 
and later on of materialistic utilitarianism, have resulted in an 
almost complete neglect of the personal and social element in 
education, and in the preponderance of abstract educational 
aims, such as knowledge and professional ability. Pestalozzi's 
idea of education, deeply rooted in the Christian understanding 
of life, and therefore putting responsible personality and love in 
the first place, has been entirely misunderstood or neglected, in 
spite of its fame. 

It is only in the last place in a Christian programme of civilisa- 
tion that we find what in the humanistic programme comes 
first : the so-called higher culture, embracing the purely spiritual 
elements, such as science and art. The expression, " higher 
culture is justified in so far as in this realm the activity of the 
spirit is most remote from animalic urge and biological neces- 
sity. It is also, and for the same reason, the field of a spiritual 
ilite* It is the realm of spiritual creativity. While in principle 



I36 CHRISTIAN CIVILISATION AND CULTURE [LECT. 

everyone can be good, only a few can be creative; the creative 
genjjis is the exception, and it is he who produces the works of 
which we mostly think when speaking of culture. It is, how- 
ever, characteristic of the Christian conception of culture and 
civilisation to give these peak manifestations less importance 
than does idealistic humanism, for it is not science, art and 
spiritual activity which give life its truly human content, but 
love. 

This specific order of values, however, does not prevent the 
Christian from giving art and science, as well as so-called higher 
education, a characteristic aim and meaning. .Science as the 
search for truth, and art as the creation of the beautiful, are 
given the highest possible meaning : divine service. Wherever 
truth is known, something of the mystery of creation is revealed. 
The true scientist is a servant of God. To know and to acknow- 
ledge God is not a hindrance but, on the contrary, a help, in the 
search for truth. It keeps us from false absolutism and 
relativism, from idolatry of reason, and from sceptical despair. 
The scientist working, like Kepler, under highest command and 
for the honour of God is free from mean ambition and jealousy. 
The same is true of the artist. There is nothing which ennobles 
and purifies his creative powers so much as the conviction that 
he is a servant of God, called to praise the Creator and to mani- 
fest the secret which unites spirit and nature. It need not be 
proved, because it is proved already by history, that art can never 
rise higher than the point where the artist takes his highest 
inspiration devoutly as a gift of the Creator. There alone art is 
safeguarded from false aestheticism and idolatry of genius, as 
well as from that formalism and barbarism which lead to the 
ruin of art. 

The second direction which Christian faith gives to the higher 
culture is service of man. To be sure, science remains sound 
only where it is not dominated by the principle of utility. Art 
degenerates if it becomes subservient to any aim outside of 
itself. Purpose-free science and purpose-free art are identical 
with true science and true art. All the same, if this is taken as 
the last word, a perilous dualism results; somewhere there must 



X] THE SERVICE OF ART AND SCIENCE 1%J 

be a urfity between truth and beauty on the one side and the 
good life on the other. This connection, however, must b« very 
high if it is not to degrade art and science. This highest unity 
is God. God is the origin of truth and beauty, as well as the 
Creator of nature and the body, and the source of the moral 
order. Apart from God there is no possibility of uniting the 
principle of service with the principle of disinterested search for 
truth and beauty. God alone, theonomy, is the guarantee that 
such disinterested quest, such " autonomy " of science and art, 
does not contradict ethical standards. 

It is not at ail necessary that art, in order to honour God, must 
be "religious" art or Church art; neither is it necessary that 
science should be subordinated to theology. Science and art 
serve men best if they remain true to their own laws. They 
must be " autonomous But if this autonomy is ultimate, 
final, it cannot but degenerate into sterile inhuman intellectualist 
" scientism " ajjd into Vart -pour Vart aestheticism. If, how- 
ever, their autonomy is understood as theonomy, they keep 
their independence and yet are united to natural life and ethical 
principles by a c unity standing above all of them. This is not 
mere theory but historical experience. It is what we have learnt 
from the greatest men of science and of art. Filled with rever- 
ence for God, the ultimate source of truth and beauty, they 
remained true to the immanent law of truth and beauty. And 
in doing so, they served their fellow men much better than by 
any direct subordination to moral or utilitarian requirements. 
That is to say, the different spheres of higher culture have their 
autonomy, but at the same time they are linked with each other, 
not directly, not horizontally, but vertically, communicating 
with each other only by reference to the same source of their 
autonomy. 

One last characteristic trait of the Christian idea of civilisation 
and culture relates to these two words as such. Why do we 
need two words, and which should take precedence? As 
everyone knows, there is a remarkable difference, again, between 
the German use of the words, on the one hand, and the English 
and French use on the other. In German it has become 



138 CHRISTIAN CIVILISATION AND CULTURE [LECT. 

customary to think of Zivilisation as something much lower 
than *Kultur, meaning primarily the technical aspect of what the 
English and French call civilisation. This degradation of 
" civilisation " is the result of that onesicbd idealistic spirituali- 
sation which puts the purely spiritual things in the first place, 
calling them " higher " culture. The French and particularly 
the English use of words, however, is based on the high estimate 
of the civic element in all civilisation, the social and political 
element of justice and freedom, without which no true culture 
can exist. We need not repeat what has already been said in 
favour of this latter conception. It is a Christian heritage. 
Because in the Christian conception of man the relation between 
man and man is more important than the so-called " higher " 
culture, the problems of social and political order and, above all, 
those of marriage, family, and education, are basic in the 
Christian conception of civilisation and culture. We cannot put 
so-called higher culture in the first place, and therefore we cannot 
agree that civilisation be subordinated to culture. If we had to 
use one word only, we would rather use the word civilisation 
than the word culture, as we have done so far. 

Having thus sketched the Christian idea of civilisation in 
rough outline, we can now, in conclusion, turn back to the 
very beginning of our lectures, to the question: What are 
the chances of a Christian civilisation in our age? The 
prospect seems to be very bad indeed, and we should not in 
closing make ourselves guilty of a false and facile optimism. 
Yet pessimism cannot be our attitude either. There is a German 
proverb: Des Menschen Verlegenheiten sind Gottes Gelegen- 
heiten. 1 The terrible perspectives which are placed before us by 
the dechristianisation of the world during the past two centuries 
. have opened the eyes of many of our contemporaries to the true 
foundations of civilisation and to the importance of the Christian 
tradition. It is not only the physicists and technicians, terri- 
fied by their latest results, that have become conscious of the 
imminent peril of human civilisation and are looking out for a 
new spiritual basis of life, but also the jurists, the sociologists, 

* M^R*s extremity, God's opportunity. 



X] WHAT OF THE OUTLOOK? 1 39 

the psychologists, and — last, not least — the artists and poets. 
The lowest point of secularisation seems to be behind us. Iji all 
spheres of civilised life there is a new search for the foundation 
of a really human civilisation, and in this search the Christian 
tradition is rediscovered. I do not prophesy an epoch of general 
return to Christianity, any more than I accept the myth of the 
Christian culture of the past. If I did, I should be guilty of a 
new kind of determinism, mistaking for predictable necessity 
what is a matter of decision. Mankind is confronted with a 
decision of incomparable consequence. All we can say is this : 
^the decision may be made in the right sense, there is nothing 
impossible about it; but whether it will be taken in the right 
sei^se, nobody can know. It is sufficient that everyone who sees 
it should do what is required of him. 



EPILOGUE 



CHRISTIANITY BEYOND CIVILISATION 

THE gospel of the redemption and salvation of the world 
in Jesus Christ is not meant to be a programme"^ for any 
kind of civilisation or culture. Civilisation and culture, 
even at their best, are temporal; they belong to this earthly life. 
The gospel, however, is the revelation of eternal life. Civilisa- 
tions and cultures come and go, just as man in his visible 
appearance comes and goes. But man as a person is not meant 
to pass away; he is destined by the Creator for eternity. That 
is why he is more than any culture or civilisation. The gospel 
of Jesus Christ is the revelation of this his destiny beyond and 
above historical life. To believe in this gospel means to be 
incorporated into the invisible world which is " beyond " and 
" above " the visible, that world the full manifestation of which 
will be the end of this visible historical world, with all its 
civilisations and cultures. 

That is why the first and main concern of the Christian can 
never be civilisation and culture. His main concern is his 
relation to God in Jesus Christ, that life which is "hid with 
Christ his sharing in God's forgiving mercy in the fellowship 
with those who also, like himself, have become participants of 
God's revelation and redemption and of his firm hope in the 
fulfilment of God's promise of the eternal kingdom. This 
Christian faith therefore cuts across all forms of historical life 
with their different forms of civilisation, good and bad. It 
is not identical with any of them and none of them can ever 
be thought of as its adequate expression, All the differ- 
ences between forms of civilised and cultural life are relative, 
whilst their distance from the eternal kingdom of God is 
absolute. 

The Christian, then, and the fellowship of the Christians; are 

140 



THE FINAL GOAL 141 

ultimately independent of all the changes — for good or evil — 
within the sphere of civilisation. They stand on a rock which no 
^historical changes can move. Even the most terrifying antici- 
pations for the further development of civilisation cannot — 
ultimately — shake, neither can any progress towards good 
confirm — ultimately — their faith in the final goal which God 
has set for all his universe and all mankind. The things of 
civilisation and culture, even their best, belong to "the flesh 
which ^cannot inherit immortal life". The Christian Church 
knows that no progress in the sphere of civilisation and culture 
can reach that goal of history beyond history, and that no set- 
backs, not even the complete destruction of civilised life, can 
defect history from that ultimate goal which is beyond itself. 
In this sense then the Christian faith is indeed " other-worldly " 
and the Church should not be ashamed of saying so. 

It is by this other-worldliness that true Christianity is " the 
salt of the earth " and " the light of the world It is by its 
independence of the course of history that it can best serve the 
cause of a truly human civilisation and culture. It is by her 
very other-woridliness that the primitive Church of the first 
centuries gave the impulses for the best of those new forms of 
life which, with caution, may be called Christian civilisation. 
It is the paradox of the Christian existence that its other-worldli- 
ness proves to be the strongest force of renewal and preservation 
in the different domains of cultural life. Why this is so and 
how, we have tried to show in these lectures. God wants us to 
be in this world and to do our best in humanising and person- 
alising its life. But we can render this service only when we 
know that this is not our primary but only our secondary task, 
as we keep ourselves free from all illusions of universal progress 
and of despair in sight of general degeneration and dissolution. 
Utopias are poor substitutes for real hope and despair is their 
almost necessary concomitant. In all times of Christian history 
it was those Christian men and groups of men who did not 
believe in progress who did the most to move the world in real 
progress. This creative and constructive contribution of 
Christianity to civilisation is, so to speak, a mere by-product of 



142 CHRISTIANITY BEYOND CIVILISATION [LECT. 

real Christian faith, but it is a necessary by-product by which 
its cfeeper reality can be gauged. 

The problems of our present-day civilisatiofi are so grave and 
pressing that even Christians may thinly it their duty to make - 
them their primary concern and to consider belief in eternity as 
a kind of luxury. They are utterly wrong. The problems of our 
day have become so incomparably complicated and difficult just 
because people do not believe in eternal life any more. They are 
seized by a kind of time-panic. Not believing in the "eternal 
Kingdom they try to make this world a paradise and by doing 
so they create a state of things which is more akin to hell than^ 
to heaven. The loss of real hope, i.e. hope in eternal life, creates 
Utopias, and Utopias may be considered as one of the main repots 
of our present-day chaos. If man loses the real hope he has to 
choose between illusions and despair, and mostly he vacillates 
between the two in a spiritual condition which the psychiatrists 
describe as " depressive-maniac ". ^ 

The real Christian is sober in his expectation for and from this 
temporal world. He knows that it cannot transcend its limits 
of death and sin. He knows also that it is the place where God 
can do marvellous things. He feels himself called upon by his 
Lord as His instrument by Whom he wants to do those things 
which man without the divine faith, love and hope cannot do. 
Still he knows that by all his doings the most he can achieve is 
to " salt " and to " leaven " the world, but not to save it from 
death and sin. And if he is a real Christian, he always is 
deeply conscious of his own shortcomings. 

The Christian faith and hope in eternal life has been dis- 
credited, not without reason, during the last century, through 
having been used as a cheap substitute for justice and social 
responsibility. We cannot blame the Marxists for calling 
religion an " opium for the people " because that is what they all 
too often found it to be. There is, indeed, a false Christian 
other-worldliness which has done more harm to the cause of 
Christ than most other vices of Christian individuals and 
groups. But abusus non tollit usum. The false understanding 
of other-worldliness does not make the true other-worldliness 



Xl] T&E ULTIMATE DECISION I43 

false. Christianity which is no more other-worldly has erased 
to be Christian. This other-worldliness is the root of ^true 
realism which hopes and works in and for this world without 
^illusion and without despair. 

God has cheated man for both this world and the world to 
come. He therefore made him capable of creating civilisation 
and culture and gave him the final destiny beyond them. It 
is the knowledge of this final destiny which makes Christianity 
capable' 1 of giving civilisation and culture an element which 
otherwise they do not have, the element of radical personalism 
and communaUsm, which are at bottom the same thing. A 
civilisation and a culture, as it would grow out of a truly 
Christian community, would be characterised by personalism 
and communalised creativity. But this very personalism and 
communalism is entirely the outcome of that faith and hope 
which have their roots as well as their aim beyond history. 



ABERDEEN ! THE UNIVERSITY PRESS